Theory of conjoint measurement

Theory of conjoint measurement

The theory of conjoint measurement (also known as conjoint measurement or additive conjoint measurement) is a general, formal theory of continuous quantity. It was independently discovered by the French economist Gerard Debreu (1960) and by the American mathematical psychologist R. Duncan Luce and statistician John Tukey (Luce & Tukey, 1964).

The theory concerns the situation where at least two natural attributes, A and X, non-interactively relate to a third attribute, P. It is not required that A, X or P be already known to be quantities. Via specific relations between the levels of P, it can be established that P, A and X are continuous quantities. Hence the theory of conjoint measurement can be used to quantify attributes in empirical circumstances where it is not possible to combine the levels of the attributes using a side-by-side operation or concatenation. The quantification of psychological attributes such as attitudes, cognitive abilities and utility is therefore logically plausible. This means that the scientific measurement of psychological attributes is possible. That is, like physical quantities, a magnitude of a psychological quantity may possibly be expressed as the product of a real number and a unit magnitude.

Application of the theory of conjoint measurement in psychology, however, has been limited. It has been argued that this is due to the high level of formal mathematics involved (e.g., Cliff, 1992) and that the theory cannot account for the "noisy" data typically discovered in psychological research (e.g., Perline, Wright & Wainer, 1979). It has been argued that the Rasch model is a stochastic variant of the theory of conjoint measurement (e.g., Brogden, 1977; Embretson & Reise, 2000; Fischer, 1995; Keats, 1967; Kline, 1998; Scheiblechner, 1999), however, this has been disputed (e.g., Karabatsos, 2001; Kyngdon, 2008). Order restricted methods for conducting probabilistic tests of the cancellation axioms of conjoint measurement have been developed in the past decade (e.g., Karabatsos, 2001; Davis-Stober, 2009).

The theory of conjoint measurement is not to be confused with conjoint analysis, which is a statistical research methodology employed in marketing. Conjoint analysis does not at all concern continuous quantity or scientific measurement.


Contents

Historical overview

In the 1930s, the British Association for the Advancement of Science established the Ferguson Committee to investigate the possibility of psychological attributes being measured scientifically. The British physicist and measurement theorist Norman Robert Campbell was an influential member of the committee.In its Final Report (Ferguson, et al, 1940), Campbell and the Committee concluded that because psychological attributes were not capable of sustaining concatenation operations, such attributes could not be continuous quantities. Therefore, they could not be measured scientifically. This had important ramifications for psychology, the most significant of these being the creation in 1946 of the operational theory of measurement by Harvard psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens. Stevens' non-scientific theory of measurement is widely held as definitive in psychology and the behavioural sciences generally (Michell, 1999).

Whilst the German mathematician Otto Hölder (1901) anticipated features of the theory of conjoint measurement, it was not until the publication of Luce & Tukey's seminal 1964 paper that the theory received its first complete exposition. Luce & Tukey's presentation was algebraic and is therefore considered more general than Debreu's (1960) topological work, the latter being a special case of the former (Luce & Suppes, 2002). In the first article of the inaugural issue of the Journal of Mathematical Psychology, Luce & Tukey (1964) proved that via the theory of conjoint measurement, attributes not capable of concatenation could be quantified. N.R. Campbell and the Ferguson Committee were thus proven wrong. That a given psychological attribute is a continuous quantity is a logically coherent and empirically testable hypothesis.

Appearing in the next issue of the same journal were important papers by Dana Scott (1964), who proposed a hierarchy of cancellation conditions for the indirect testing of the solvability and Archimedean axioms, and David Krantz (1964) who connected the Luce & Tukey work to that of Hölder (1901).

Work soon focused on extending the theory of conjoint measurement to involve more than just two attributes. Krantz (1968) and Amos Tversky (1967) developed what became known as polynomial conjoint measurement, with Krantz (1968) providing a schema with which to construct conjoint measurement structures of three or more attributes. Later, the theory of conjoint measurement (in its two variable, polynomial and n-component forms) received a thorough and highly technical treatment with the publication of the first volume of Foundations of Measurement, which Krantz, Luce, Tversky and philosopher Patrick Suppes cowrote (Krantz, Luce, Suppes & Tversky, 1971).

Shortly after the publication of Krantz, et al., (1971), work focused upon developing an "error theory" for the theory of conjoint measurement. Studies were conducted into the number of conjoint arrays that supported only single cancellation and both single and double cancellation (Arbuckle & Larimer, 1976; McClelland, 1977). Later enumeration studies focused on polynomial conjoint measurement (Karabatsos & Ullrich, 2002; Ullrich & Wilson, 1993). These studies found that it is highly unlikely that the axioms of the theory of conjoint measurement are satisfied at random, provided that more than three levels of at least of one the component attributes has been identified.

Joel Michell (1988) later identified that the "no test" class of tests of the double cancellation axiom was empty. Any instance of double cancellation is thus either an acceptance or a rejection of the axiom. Michell also wrote at this time a non-technical introduction to the theory of conjoint measurement (Michell, 1990) which also contained a schema for deriving higher order cancellation conditions based upon Scott's (1964) work. Using Michell's schema, Ben Richards (Kyngdon & Richards, 2007) discovered that some instances of the triple cancellation axiom are "incoherent" as they contradict the single cancellation axiom. Moreover, he identified many instances of the triple cancellation which are trivially true if double cancellation is supported.

The axioms of the theory of conjoint measurement are not stochastic; and given the ordinal constraints placed on data by the cancellation axioms, order restricted inference methodology must be used (Iverson & Falmagne, 1985). George Karabatsos and his associates (Karabatsos, 2001; Karabatsos & Sheu, 2004) developed a Bayesian Markov Chain Monte Carlo methodology for psychometric applications. Karabatsos & Ullrich (2002) demonstrated how this framework could be extended to polynomial conjoint structures. Karabatsos (2005) generalised this work with his multinomial Dirichlet framework, which enabled the probabilistic testing of many non-stochastic theories of mathematical psychology. More recently, Clintin Davis-Stober (2009) developed a frequentist framework for order restricted inference that can also be used to test the cancellation axioms.

Perhaps the most notable (Kyngdon, in press) use of the theory of conjoint measurement was in the prospect theory proposed by the Israeli - American psychologists Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tverksy (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). Prospect theory was a theory of decision making under risk and uncertainty which accounted for choice behaviour such as the Allais Paradox. David Krantz wrote the formal proof to prospect theory using the theory of conjoint measurement. In 2002, Kahneman received the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics for prospect theory (Birnbaum, 2008).

Measurement and quantification

The classical / standard definition of measurement

In physics and metrology, the standard definition of measurement is the estimation of the ratio between a magnitude of a continuous quantity and a unit magnitude of the same kind (de Boer, 1994/95; Emerson, 2008). For example, the statement "Peter's hallway is 4m long" expresses a measurement of an hitherto unknown length magnitude (the hallway's length) as the ratio of the unit (the metre in this case) to the length of the hallway. The real number "4" is a real number in the strict mathematical sense of this term.

For some other quantities, it is easier or has been convention to estimate ratios between attribute differences. Consider temperature, for example. In the familiar everyday instances, temperature is measured using instruments calibrated in either the Fahrenheit or Celsius scales. What are really being measured with such instruments are the magnitudes of temperature differences. For example, Anders Celsius defined the unit of the Celsius scale to be 1/100th of the difference in temperature between the freezing and boiling points of water at sea level. A midday temperature measurement of 20 degrees Celsius is simply the ratio of the Celsius unit to the midday temperature.

Formally expressed, a scientific measurement is:

 Q = r \times [Q]

where Q is the magnitude of the quantity, r is a real number and [Q] is a unit magnitude of the same kind.

Extensive and intensive quantity

Length is a quantity for which natural concatenation operations exist. That is, we can combine in a side by side fashion lengths of rigid steel rods, for example, such that the additive relations between lengths is readily observed. If we have four 1m lengths of such rods, we can place them end to end to produce a length of 4m. Quantities capable of concatenation are known as extensive quantities and include mass, time, electrical resistance and plane angle. These are known as base quantities in physics and metrology.

Temperature is a quantity for which there is an absence of concatenation operations. We cannot pour a volume of water of temperature 40 degrees Celsius into another bucket of water at 20 degrees Celsius and expected to have a volume of water with a temperature of 60 degrees Celsius. Temperature is therefore an intensive quantity.

Psychological attributes, like temperature, are considered to be intensive as no way of concatenating such attributes has been found. But this is not to say that such attributes are not quantifiable. The theory of conjoint measurement provides a theoretical means of doing this.

Theory

Consider two natural attributes A, and X. It is not known that either A or X is a continuous quantity, or that both of them are. Let a, b, and c represent three independent, identifiable levels of A; and let x, y and z represent three independent, identifiable levels of X. A third attribute, P, consists of the nine ordered pairs of levels of A and X. That is, (a, x), (b, y),..., (c, z) (see Figure 1). The quantification of A, X and P depends upon the behaviour of the relation holding upon the levels of P. These are relations are presented as axioms in the theory of conjoint measurement.

Single cancellation or independence axiom

Figure One: Graphical representation of the single cancellation axiom. It can be seen that a > b because (a, x) > (b, x), (a, y) > (b, y) and (a, z) > (b, z).

The single cancellation axiom is as follows. The relation upon P satisfies single cancellation if and only if for all a and b in A, and x in X, (a, x) > (b, x) is implied for every w in X such that (a, w) > (b, w). Similarly, for all x and y in X and a in A, (a, x) > (a, y) is implied for every d in A such that (d, x) > (d, y). What this means is that if any two levels, a, b, are ordered, then this order holds irrespective of each and every level of X. The same holds for any two levels, x and y of X with respect to each and every level of A.

Single cancellation is so-called because a single common factor of two levels of P cancel out to leave the same ordinal relationship holding on the remaining elements. For example, a cancels out of the inequality (a, x) > (a, y) as it is common to boths sides, leaving x > y. Krantz, et al., (1971) originally called this axiom independence, as the ordinal relation between two levels of an attribute is independent of any and all levels of the other attribute. However, given that the term independence causes confusion with statistical concepts of independence, single cancellation is the preferable term. Figure One is a graphical representation of one instance of single cancellation.

Satisfaction of the single cancellation axiom is necessary, but not sufficient, for the quantification of attributes A and X. It only demonstrates that the levels of A, X and P are ordered. Informally, single cancellation does not sufficiently constrain the order upon the levels of P to quantify A and X. For example, consider the ordered pairs (a, x), (b, x) and (b, y). If single cancellation holds then (a, x) > (b, x) and (b, x) > (b, y). Hence via transitivity (a, x) > (b, y). The relation between these latter two ordered pairs, informally a left-leaning diagonal, is determined by the satisfaction of the single cancellation axiom, as are all the "left leaning diagonal" relations upon P.

Double cancellation axiom

Figure Two: A Luce - Tukey instance of double cancellation, in which the consequent inequality (broken line arrow) does not contradict the direction of both antecedent inequalities (solid line arrows), so supporting the axiom.

Single cancellation does not determine the order of the "right-leaning diagonal" relations upon P. Even though by transitivity and single cancellation it was established that (a, x) > (b, y), the relationship between (a, y) and (b, x) remains undetermined. It could be that either (b, x) > (a, y) or (a, y) > (b, x) and such ambiguity cannot remain unresolved.

The double cancellation axiom concerns a class of such relations upon P in which the common terms of two antecedent inequalities cancel out to produce a third inequality. Consider the instance of double cancellation graphically represented by Figure Two. The antecedent inequalities of this particular instance of double cancellation are:

\left(a, y\right) > \left(b, x\right)

and

\left(b, z\right)> \left(c, y\right).

Given that:

 \left(a, y\right) > \left(b, x\right)

is true if and only if a + y > b + x; and

\left(b, z\right) > \left(c, y\right)

is true if and only if b + z > c + y, it follows that:

a + y + b + z > b + x + c + y.

Cancelling the common terms results in:

\left(a, z\right)> \left(c, x\right).

Hence double cancellation can only obtain when A and X are quantities.

Double cancellation is satisfied if and only if the consequent inequality does not contradict the antecedent inequalities. For example, if the consequent inequality above was:

\left(a, z\right)< \left(c, x\right), or alternatively,

\left(a, z\right)= \left(c, x\right),

then double cancellation would be violated (Michell, 1988) and it could not be concluded that A and X are quantities.

Double cancellation concerns the behaviour of the "right leaning diagonal" relations on P as these are not logically entailed by single cancellation. Michell (2009) discovered that when the levels of A and X approach infinity, then the number of right leaning diagonal relations is half of the number of total relations upon P. Hence if A and X are quantities, half of the number of relations upon P are due to ordinal relations upon A and X and half are due to additive relations upon A and X (Michell, 2009).

The number of instances of double cancellation is contingent upon the number of levels identified for both A and X. If there are n levels of A and m of X, then the number of instances of double cancellation is n! × m!. Therefore, if n = m = 3, then 3! × 3! = 6 × 6 = 36 instances in total of double cancellation. However, all but 6 of these instances are trivially true if single cancellation is true, and if anyone of these 6 instances is true, then all of them are true. One such instance is that shown in Figure Two. Michell (1988) calls this a Luce - Tukey instance of double cancellation. If single cancellation has been tested upon a set of data first and is established, then only the Luce - Tukey instances of double cancellation need to be tested. For n levels of A and m of X, the number of Luce - Tukey double cancellation instances is \tbinom{n}{3}\tbinom{m}{3}. For example, if n = m = 4, then there are 16 such instances. If n = m = 5 then there are 100. The greater the number of levels in both A and X, the less probable it is that the cancellation axioms are satisfied at random (Arbuckle & Larimer, 1976; McClelland, 1977) and the more stringent test of quantity the application of conjoint measurement becomes.

Solvability and Archimedean axioms

Figure Three: An instance of triple cancellation.

The single and double cancellation axioms by themselves are not sufficient to establish continuous quantity. Other conditions must also be introduced to ensure continuity. These are the solvability and Archimedean conditions.

Solvability means that for any three elements of a, b, x and y, the fourth exists such that the equation a x = b y is solved, hence the name of the condition. Solvability essentially is the requirement that each level P has an element in A and an element in X. Solvability reveals something about the levels of A and X - they are either dense like the real numbers or equally spaced like the integers (Krantz, et al, 1971).

The Archimedean condition is as follows. Let I be a set of consecutive integers, either finite or infinite, positive or negative. The levels of A form a standard sequence if and only if there exists x and y in X where xy and for all integers i and i + 1 in I:

\left(a_i, x\right) = \left(a_{i+1}, y\right).

What this basically means is that if x is greater than y, for example, there are levels of A which can be found which makes two relevant ordered pairs, the levels of P, equal.

The Archimedean condition argues that there is no infinitely greatest level of P and so hence there is no greatest level of either A or X. This condition is a definition of continuity given by the ancient Greek mathematician Archimedes whom wrote that “Further, of unequal lines, unequal surfaces, and unequal solids, the greater exceeds the less by such a magnitude as, when added to itself, can be made to exceed any assigned magnitude among those which are comparable with one another ” (On the Sphere and Cylinder, Book I, Assumption 5). Archimedes recognised that for any two magnitudes of a continuous quantity, one being lesser than the other, the lesser could be multiplied by a whole number such that it equalled the greater magnitude. Euclid stated the Archimedean condition as an axiom in Book V of the Elements, in which Euclid presented his theory of continuous quantity and measurement.

As they involve infinitistic concepts, the solvability and Archimedean axioms are not amenable to direct testing in any finite empirical situation. But this does not entail that these axioms cannot be empirically tested at all. Scott's (1964) finite set of cancellation conditions can be used to indirectly test these axioms; the extent of such testing being empirically determined. For example, if both A and X possess three levels, the highest order cancellation axiom within Scott’s (1964) hierarchy that indirectly tests solvability and Archimedeaness is double cancellation. With four levels it is triple cancellation (Figure 3). If such tests are satisfied, the construction of standard sequences in differences upon A and X are possible. Hence these attributes may be dense as per the real numbers or equally spaced as per the integers (Krantz, et al., 1971). In other words, A and X are continuous quantities.

Relation to the scientific definition of measurement

Satisfaction of the conditions of conjoint measurement means that measurements of the levels of A and X can be expressed as either ratios between magnitudes or ratios between magnitude differences. It is most commonly interpreted as the latter, given that most behavioural scientists consider that their tests and surveys "measure" attributes on so-called "interval scales" (Kline, 1998). That is, they believe tests do not identify absolute zero levels of psychological attributes.

Formally, if P, A and X form an additive conjoint structure, then there exist functions from A and X into the real numbers such that for a and b in A and x and y in X:

\left(a, x \right)\succsim\left(b, y \right)\iff \phi_A \left(a\right) + \phi_X \left(x\right)\geqslant\phi_A \left(b\right) + \phi_X \left(y\right).

If \phi'_A \, and \phi'_X \, are two other real valued functions satisfying the above expression, there exist \alpha > 0, \beta_A \, and \beta_X \, real valued constants satisfying:

\phi'_A = \alpha \phi_A + \beta_A \, and \phi'_X = \alpha \phi_X + \beta_X \, .

That is, \phi'_A, \phi_A, \phi'_X \, and \phi_X \, are measurements of A and X unique up to affine transformation (i.e. each is an interval scale in Stevens’ (1946) parlance). The mathematical proof of this result is given in Krantz, et al. (1971, pp. 261–266).

This means that the levels of A and X are magnitude differences measured relative to some kind of unit difference. Each level of P is a difference between the levels of A and X. However, it is not clear from the literature as to how a unit could be defined within an additive conjoint context. van der Ven (1980) proposed a scaling method for conjoint structures but he also did not discuss the unit.

The theory of conjoint measurement, however, is not restricted to the quantification of differences. If each level of P is a product of a level of A and a level of X, then P is another different quantity whose measurement is expressed as a magnitude of A per unit magnitude of X. For example, A consists of masses and X consists of volumes, then P consists of densities measured as mass per unit of volume. In such cases, it would appear that one level of A and one level of X must be identified as a tentative unit prior to the application of conjoint measurement.

If each level of P is the sum of a level of A and a level of X, then P is the same quantity as A andX. For example, A and X are lengths so hence must be P. All three must therefore be expressed in the same unit. In such cases, it would appear that a level of either A or X must be tentatively identified as the unit. Hence it would seem that application of conjoint measurement requires some prior descriptive theory of the relevant natural system.

Applications of Conjoint Measurement

Empirical applications of the theory of conjoint measurement have been sparse (Cliff, 1992; Michell, 2009).

Levelt, Riemersma & Bunt (1972) applied the theory to the psychophysics of binaural loudness. They found the double cancellation axiom was rejected. Gigerenzer & Strube (1983) conducted a similar investigation and replicated Levelt, et al' (1972) findings.

Michell (1990) applied the theory to L.L. Thurstone's (1927) theory of paired comparisons, multidimensional scaling and Coombs' (1964) theory of unidimensional unfolding. He found support of the cancellation axioms only with Coombs' (1964) theory. However, the statistical techniques employed by Michell (1990) in testing Thurstone's theory and multidimensional scaling did not take into consideration the ordinal constraints imposed by the cancellation axioms (van der Linden, 1994).

Johnson (2001), Kyngdon (2006), Michell (1994) and Sherman (1993) tested the cancellation axioms of upon the interstimulus midpoint orders obtained by the use of Coombs' (1964) theory of unidimensional unfolding. Coombs' theory in all three studies was applied to a set of six statements. These authors found that the axioms were satisfied, however, these were applications biased towards a positive result. With six stimuli, the probability of an interstimulus midpoint order satisfying the double cancellation axioms at random is .5874 (Michell, 1994). This is not an unlikely event. Kyngdon & Richards (2007) employed eight statements and found the interstimulus midpoint orders rejected the double cancellation condition.

Perline, Wright and Wainer (1979) applied conjoint measurement to item response data to a convict parole questionnaire and to intelligence test data gathered from Danish troops. They found considerable violation of the cancellation axioms in the parole questionnaire data, but not in the intelligence test data. Moreover, they recorded the supposed "no - test" instances of double cancellation. Interpreting these correctly as instances in support of double cancellation (Michell, 1988), the results of Perline, et al (1979) are better than what they believed.

Stankov & Cregan (1993) applied conjoint measurement to performance on sequence completion tasks. The columns of their conjoint arrays (X) were defined by the demand placed upon working memory capacity through increasing numbers of working memory place keepers in letter series completion tasks. The rows were defined by levels of motivation (A), which consisted in different amount of times available for compelting the test. Their data (P) consisted of completion times and average number of series correct. They found support for the cancellation axioms, however, their study was biased by the small size of the conjoint arrays (3 × 3 is size) and by statistical techniques that did not take into consideration the ordinal restrictions imposed by the cancellation axioms.

Kyngdon (in press) used Karabatsos' (2001) order restricted inference framework to test a conjoint matrix of reading item response proportions (P) where the examinee reading ability comprised the rows of the conjoint array (A) and the difficulty of the reading items formed the columns of the array (X). The levels of reading ability were identified via raw total test score and the levels of reading item difficulty were identified by the Lexile Framework for Reading (Stenner, Burdick, Sanford & Burdick, 2006). Kyngdon found that satisfaction of the cancellation axioms was obtained only through permutation of the matrix in a manner inconsistent with the putative Lexile measures of item difficulty. Kyngdon also tested simulated ability test response data using polynomial conjoint measurement. The data were generated using Humphry's extended frame of reference Rasch model (Humphry & Andrich, 2008). He found support of distributive, single and double cancellation consistent with a distributive polynomial conjoint structure in three variables (Krantz & Tversky, 1971).

See also

References

  • Arbuckle, J. & Larimer, J. (1976). The number of two-way tables satisfying certain additivity axioms. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 12, 89–100.
  • Birnbaum, M.H. (2008). New paradoxes of risky decision making. Psychological Review, 115, 463-501.
  • Brogden, H.E. (1977). The Rasch model, the law of comparative judgement and additive conjoint measurement. Psychometrika, 42, 631-634.
  • Cliff, N. (1992). Abstract measurement theory and the revolution that never happened. Psychological Science, 3, 186-190.
  • Coombs, C.H. (1964). A Theory of Data. New York: Wiley.
  • Davis-Stober, C.P. (2009). Analysis of multinomial models under inequality constraints: applications to measurement theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 1-13.
  • Debreu, G. (1960). Topological methods in cardinal utility theory. In K.J. Arrow, S. Karlin and P. Suppes (eds.), Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, Stanford University Press, pp. 16 – 26.
  • Embretson, S.E. & Reise, S.P. (2000). Item response theory for psychologists. NJ: Erlbaum.
  • Emerson, W.H. (2008). On quantity calculus and units of measurement. Metrologia, 45, 134–138.
  • Fischer, G. (1995). Derivations of the Rasch model. In G. Fischer and I.W. Molenaar (Eds.), Rasch models: Foundations, recent developments, and applications (pp. 15–38). New York: Springer.
  • Gigerenzer, G. & Strube, G. (1983). Are there limits to binaural additivity of loudness? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 9, 126–136.
  • Grayson, D.A. (1988). Two-group classification and latent trait theory: scores with monotone likelihood ratio. Psychometrika, 53, 383–392.
  • Hölder, O. (1901). Die Axiome der Quantität und die Lehre vom Mass. Berichte uber die Verhandlungen der Koeniglich Sachsischen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig, Mathematisch-Physikaliche Klasse, 53, 1–46. (Part 1 translated by J. Michell and C. Ernst (1996). The axioms of quantity and the theory of measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 40, 235–252).
  • Humphry, S.M. & Andrich, D. (2008). Understanding the unit in the Rasch model. Journal of Applied Measurement, 9, 249-264.
  • Iverson, G. & Falmagne, J.C. (1985). Statistical issues in measurement. Mathematical Social Sciences, 10, 131–153.
  • Johnson, T. (2001). Controlling the effect of stimulus context change on attitude statements using Michell’s binary tree procedure. Australian Journal of Psychology, 53, 23-28.
  • Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.
  • Karabatsos, G. (2001). The Rasch model, additive conjoint measurement, and new models of probabilistic measurement theory. Journal of Applied Measurement, 2, 389–423.
  • Karabatsos, G. (2005). The exchangeable multinomial model as an approach for testing axioms of choice and measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 49, 51–69.
  • Karabatsos, G., & Sheu, C.F. (2004). Bayesian order constrained inference for dichotomous models of unidimensional non-parametric item response theory. Applied Psychological Measurement, 28, 110–125.
  • Karabatsos, G. & Ullrich, J.R. (2002). Enumerating and testing conjoint measurement models. Mathematical Social Sciences, 43, 485–504.
  • Krantz, D.H. (1964). Conjoint measurement: the Luce - Tukey axiomatisation and some extensions. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1, 248–277.
  • Krantz, D.H. (1968). A survey of measurement theory. In G.B. Danzig & A.F. Veinott (Eds.), Mathematics of the Decision Sciences, part 2 (pp. 314–350). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.
  • Keats, J.A. (1967). Test theory. Annual Review of Psychology, 18, 217–238.
  • Kline, P. (1998). The New Psychometrics: Science, psychology and measurement. London: Routledge.
  • Krantz, D.H.; Luce, R.D; Suppes, P. & Tversky, A. (1971). Foundations of Measurement, Vol. I: Additive and polynomial representations. New York: Academic Press.
  • Krantz, D.H. & Tversky, A. (1971). Conjoint measurement analysis of composition rules in psychology. Psychological Review, 78, 151-169.
  • Kyngdon, A. (in press). Plausible measurement analogies to some psychometric models of test performance. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology.
  • Kyngdon, A. (2008). The Rasch model from the perspective of the representational theory of measurement. Theory & Psychology, 18, 89-109.
  • Kyngdon, A. (2006). An empirical study into the theory of unidimensional unfolding. Journal of Applied Measurement, 7, 369-393.
  • Kyngdon, A. & Richards, B. (2007). Attitudes, order and quantity: deterministic and direct probabilistic tests of unidimensional unfolding. Journal of Applied Measurement, 8, 1–34.
  • Levelt, W. J. M., Riemersma, J. B., & Bunt, A. A. (1972) Binaural additivity of loudness. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 25, 51-68.
  • Luce, R.D., & Suppes, P. (2002). Representational measurement theory. In H. Pashler & J. Wixted (Eds.), Stevens’ handbook of experimental psychology: Vol. 4. Methodology in experimental psychology (3rd ed., pp. 1–41). New York: Wiley.
  • Luce, R.D. & Tukey, J.W. (1964). Simultaneous conjoint measurement: a new scale type of fundamental measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1, 1–27.
  • McClelland, G. (1977). A note on Arbuckle and Larimer: the number of two way tables satisfying certain additivity axioms. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 15, 292–295.
  • Michell, J. (1994). Measuring dimensions of belief by unidimensional unfolding. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 38, 224-273.
  • Michell, J. (1988). Some problems in testing the double cancellation condition in conjoint measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 32, 466–473.
  • Michell, J. (1990). An Introduction to the Logic of Psychological Measurement. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.
  • Michell, J. (2009). The psychometricians’ fallacy: Too clever by half? British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 62, 41-55.
  • Perline, R.; Wright, B.D & Wainer, H. (1979). The Rasch model as additive conjoint measurement. Applied Psychological Measurement, 3, 237-255.
  • Scheiblechner, H. (1999). Additive conjoint isotonic probabilistic models (ADISOP). Psychometrika, 64, 295-316.
  • Scott, D. (1964). Measurement models and linear inequalities. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 1, 233–247.
  • Sherman, K. (1994). The effect of change in context in Coombs’s unfolding theory. Australian Journal of Psychology, 46, 41-47.
  • Stankov, L. & Cregan, A. (1993). Quantitative and qualitative properties of an intelligence test: series completion. Learning and Individual Differences, 5, 137-169.
  • Stenner, A.J., Burdick, H., Sanford, E.E. & Burdick, D.S. How accurate are Lexile text measures? Journal of Applied Measurement,7, 307-322.
  • Stevens, S.S. (1946). On the theory of scales of measurement. Science, 103, 667–680.
  • Thurstone, L.L. (1927). A law of comparative judgement. Psychological Review, 34, 278-286.
  • Tversky, A. (1967). A general theory of polynomial conjoint measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 4, 1–20.
  • Ullrich, J.R. & Wilson, R.E. (1993). A note on the exact number of two and three way tables satisfying conjoint measurement and additivity axioms. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 37, 624–628.
  • van der Linden, W. (1994). Review of Michell (1990). Psychometrika, 59, 139-142.
  • van der Ven, A.H.G.S. (1980). Introduction to Scaling. New York: Wiley.

External resources


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Polynomial conjoint measurement — is an extension of the theory of conjoint measurement to three or more attributes. It was initially developed by the mathematical psychologists David Krantz (1968) and Amos Tversky (1967). The theory was given a comprehensive mathematical… …   Wikipedia

  • Conjoint analysis — See also: Conjoint analysis (in marketing), Conjoint analysis (in healthcare), IDDEA, Rule Developing Experimentation. Conjoint analysis, also called multi attribute compositional models or stated preference analysis, is a statistical technique… …   Wikipedia

  • Measurement — For bust/waist/hip measurement, see BWH. A typical tape measure with both metric and US units and two US pennies for comparison Measurement is the process or the result of determining the ratio of a physical quantity, such as a length, time,… …   Wikipedia

  • Level of measurement — The levels of measurement , or scales of measure are expressions that typically refer to the theory of scale types developed by the psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens. Stevens proposed his theory in a 1946 Science article titled On the theory of… …   Wikipedia

  • Units of measurement — Weights and measures redirects here. For other uses, see Weights and measures (disambiguation). The former Weights and Measures office in Seven Sisters, London A unit of measurement is a definite magnitude of a physical quantity, defined and… …   Wikipedia

  • Mathematical psychology — Psychology …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (T) — NOTOC T T duality T group T group (mathematics) T integration T norm T norm fuzzy logics T schema T square (fractal) T symmetry T table T theory T.C. Mits T1 space Table of bases Table of Clebsch Gordan coefficients Table of divisors Table of Lie …   Wikipedia

  • Measuring the Mind —   Author(s) Denny Borsboom Publisher …   Wikipedia

  • Potentially all pairwise rankings of all possible alternatives — (PAPRIKA) is a method for multi criteria decision making (MCDM) or conjoint analysis based on decision makers’ preferences as expressed using pairwise rankings of alternatives.[1][2] The PAPRIKA method – implemented via a specific type of… …   Wikipedia

  • Psychometriker — Die Psychometrie ist das Gebiet der Psychologie, das sich allgemein mit Theorie und Methode des psychologischen Messens befasst. Hauptaufgaben der Forschung sind vor allem die Entwicklung und Verbesserung von theoretischen Ansätzen des… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”