The Method of Mechanical Theorems

The Method of Mechanical Theorems

The Method of Mechanical Theorems is a work by Archimedes which contains the first attested explicit use of infinitesimals.[1] The work was originally thought to be lost, but was rediscovered in the celebrated Archimedes Palimpsest. The palimpsest includes Archimedes' account of the "mechanical method", so called because it relies on the law of the lever, which was first demonstrated by Archimedes, and of the center of gravity, which he had found for many special cases.

Archimedes did not admit infinitesimals as part of rigorous mathematics, and therefore did not publish his method in the formal treatises that contain the results. In these treatises, he proves the same theorems by exhaustion, finding rigorous upper and lower bounds which both converge to the answer required. Nevertheless, the mechanical method was what he used to discover the relations for which he later gave rigorous proofs.

Contents

Area of a parabola

To explain Archimedes' method today, it is convenient to make use of a little bit of Cartesian geometry, although this of course was unavailable at the time. His idea is to use the law of the lever to determine the areas of figures from the known center of mass of other figures. The simplest example in modern language is the area of the parabola. Archimedes uses a more elegant method, but in Cartesian language, his method is calculating the integral

 \int_0^1 x^2 \, dx,

which is 1/3 by elementary integral calculus.

To find this integral, consider balancing a triangle with the parabola. The triangle is the region in the x-y plane between the x-axis and the line y = x as x varies from 0 to 1. The parabola is the region in the x-y plane between the x-axis and y = x2, also as x varies from 0 to 1.

Slice the triangle and parabola into vertical slices, one for each value of x. Imagine that the x-axis is a lever, with a fulcrum at x=0. By the law of the lever—the mass times the distance to the fulcrum must be equal in order for two things to balance. The mass of the slice of the triangle at position x is equal to its height, to x, and it is at a distance x from the fulcrum, so that it will balance the corresponding slice of the parabola, of height x2, if it is placed at x=−1, at a distance of 1 on the other side of the fulcrum.

Since each slice balances, the whole parabola balances the whole triangle. This means that if the parabola is hung by a hook from the point x = −1, it will balance the triangle sitting between x = 0 and x = 1.

The center of mass of a triangle can be easily found by the following method, also due to Archimedes. If a median line is drawn from any one of the vertices of a triangle to the opposite edge E, the triangle will balance on the median, considered as a fulcrum. The reason is that if the triangle is divided into infinitesimal line segments parallel to E, each segment has equal length on opposite sides of the median, so balance follows by symmetry. This argument can be easily made rigorous by exhaustion by using little rectangles instead of infinitesimal lines, and this is what Archimedes does in On the Equilibrium of Planes.

So the center of mass of a triangle must be at the intersection point of the medians. For the triangle in question, one median is the line y = x/2, while a second median is the line y = 1 − x. The intersection of the two medians is at the point x = 2/3, so that the total mass of the triangle can be thought of as pushing down on this point. The total area of the triangle is 1/2, so the total torque exerted by the triangle is 1/2 times the distance to the center of mass, 2/3, which comes out to 1/3. The mass of the parabola, the area of the parabola, must then be 1/3.

This type of method can be used to find the area of an arbitrary section of a parabola, and similar arguments can be used to find the integral of any power of x, although higher powers become complicated without algebra. Archimedes only went as far as the integral of x3, which he used to find the center of mass of a hemisphere, and in other work, the center of mass of a parabola.

First proposition in the palimpsest

The curve in this figure is a parabola.

Archie1small.png

The points A and B are on the curve. The line AC is parallel to the axis of the parabola. The line BC is tangent to the parabola. The first proposition states:

The area of the triangle ABC is exactly three times the area bounded by the parabola and the secant line AB.
Proof: Let D be the midpoint of AC. The point D is the fulcrum of a lever, which is the line JB. The points J and B are at equal distances from the fulcrum. As Archimedes had shown, the center of gravity of the interior of the triangle is at a point I on the "lever" so located that DI:DB = 1:3. Therefore, it suffices to show that if the whole weight of the interior of the triangle rests at I, and the whole weight of the section of the parabola at J, the lever is in equilibrium. If the whole weight of the triangle rests at I, it exerts the same torque on the lever as if the infinitely small weight of every cross-section EH parallel to the axis of the parabola rests at the point G where it intersects the lever. Therefore, it suffices to show that if the weight of that cross-section rests at G and the weight of the cross-section EF of the section of the parabola rests at J, then the lever is in equilibrium. In other words, it suffices to show that EF:GD = EH:JD. That is equivalent to EF:DG = EH:DB. And that is equivalent to EF:EH = AE:AB. But that is just the equation of the parabola. Q.E.D.

Volume of a sphere

Again, to illuminate the mechanical method, it is convenient to use a little bit of coordinate geometry. If a sphere of radius 1 is placed at x = 1, the cross section ρS at any x between 0 and 2 is given by the following formula:

\rho_S(x) = \sqrt{x(2-x)}.\,

The mass of this cross section, for purposes of balancing on a lever, is proportional to the area:

 \pi \rho_S(x)^2 = 2\pi x - \pi x^2.\,

Archimedes then considered rotating the region between y = 0 and y = x on the x-y plane around the x-axis, to form a cone. The cross section of this cone is a circle of radius ρC

\rho_C(x) = x \,

and the area of this cross section is

\pi \rho_C^2 = \pi x^2. \,

So if slices of the cone and the sphere both are to be weighed together, the combined cross-sectional area is:

 M(x) = 2\pi x. \,

If the two slices are placed together at distance 1 from the fulcrum, their total weight would be exactly balanced by a circle of area at a distance x from the fulcrum on the other side. This means that the cone and the sphere together will balance a cylinder on the other side.

In order for the slices to balance in this argument, each slice of the sphere and the cone should be hung at a distance 1 from the fulcrum, so that the torque will be just proportional to the area. But the corresponding slice of the cylinder should be hung at position x on the other side. As x ranges from 0 to 2, the cylinder will have a center of gravity a distance 1 from the fulcrum, so all the weight of the cylinder can be considered to be at position 1. The condition of balance ensures that the volume of the cone plus the volume of the sphere is equal to the volume of the cylinder.

The volume of the cylinder is the cross section area, times the height, which is 2, or . Archimedes could also find the volume of the cone using the mechanical method, since, in modern terms, the integral involved is exactly the same as the one for area of the parabola. The volume of the cone is 1/3 its base area times the height. The base of the cone is a circle of radius 2, with area , while the height is 2, so the area is 8π / 3. Subtracting the volume of the cone from the volume of the cylinder gives the volume of the sphere:

 V_S = 4\pi - {8\over 3}\pi = {4\over 3}\pi.\,

The dependence of the volume of the sphere on the radius is obvious from scaling, although that also was not trivial to make rigorous back then. The method then gives the familiar formula for the volume of a sphere. By scaling the dimensions linearly Archimedes easily extended the volume result to spheroids.

Archimedes argument is nearly identical to the argument above, but his cylinder had a bigger radius, so that the cone and the cylinder hung at a greater distance from the fulcrum. He considered this argument to be his greatest achievement, requesting that the accompanying figure of the balanced sphere, cone, and cylinder be engraved upon his tombstone.

Surface area of a sphere

To find the surface area of the sphere, Archimedes argued that just as the area of the circle could be thought of as infinitely many infinitesimal right triangles going around the circumference (see Measurement of the Circle), the volume of the sphere could be thought of as divided into many cones with height equal to the radius and base on the surface. The cones all have the same height, so their volume is 1/3 the base area times the height.

Archimedes states that the total volume of the sphere is equal to the volume of a cone whose base has the same surface area as the sphere and whose height is the radius. There are no details given for the argument, but the obvious reason is that the cone can be divided into infinitesimal cones by splitting the base area up, and the each cone makes a contribution according to its base area, just the same as in the sphere.

Let the surface of the sphere be S. The volume of the cone with area S and height r is \scriptstyle Sr/3, which must equal the volume of the sphere: \scriptstyle 4\pi r^3/3. Therefore the surface area of the sphere must be r2, or "four times its largest circle". Archimedes proves this rigorously in On the Sphere and Cylinder.

Curvilinear shapes with rational volumes

One of the remarkable things about the Method is that Archimedes finds two shapes defined by sections of cylinders, whose volume does not involve π, despite the shapes having curvilinear boundaries. This is a central point of the investigation—certain curvilinear shapes could be rectified by ruler and compass, so that there are nontrivial rational relations between the volumes defined by the intersections of geometrical solids.

Archimedes emphasizes this in the beginning of the treatise, and invites the reader to try to reproduce the results by some other method. Unlike the other examples, the volume of these shapes is not rigorously computed in any of his other works. From fragments in the palimpsest, it appears that Archimedes did inscribe and circumscribe shapes to prove rigorous bounds for the volume, although the details have not been preserved.

The two shapes he considers are the intersection of two cylinders at right angles, which is the region of (xyz) obeying:

(2Cyl)  x^2 + y^2 <1 \;\;\; y^2 + z^2 <1

and the circular prism, which is the region obeying:

(CirP)  x^2 + y^2<1 \;\;\;\;\; 0<z<y.

Both problems have a slicing which produces an easy integral for the mechanical method. For the circular prism, cut up the x-axis into slices. The region in the y-z plane at any x is the interior of a right triangle of side length \scriptstyle \sqrt{1-x^2} whose area is \scriptstyle 1/2(1-x^2), so that the total volume is:

(CirP) \int_{-1}^1 {1\over 2} (1-x^2) \, dx

which can be easily rectified using the mechanical method. Adding to each triangular section a section of a triangular pyramid with area \scriptstyle x^2/2 balances a prism whose cross section is constant.

For the intersection of two cylinders, the slicing is lost in the manuscript, but it can be reconstructed in an obvious way in parallel to the rest of the document: if the x-z plane is the slice direction, the equations for the cylinder give that \scriptstyle x^2 < 1-y^2 while \scriptstyle z^2< 1-y^2, which defines a region which is a square in the x-z plane of side length \scriptstyle 2\sqrt{1-y^2}, so that the total volume is:

(2Cyl) \int_{-1}^1 4(1-y^2) \, dy.

And this is the same integral as for the previous example.

Other propositions in the palimpsest

A series of propositions of geometry are proved in the palimpsest by similar arguments. One theorem is that the location of a center of gravity of a hemisphere is located 5/8 of the way from the pole to the center of the sphere. This problem is notable, because it is evaluating a cubic integral.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Archimedes 1912

References

  • Archimedes (1912), The method of Archimedes recently discovered by Heiberg; a supplement to the Works of Archimedes, Cambridge University Press  (translated by Thomas Little Heath).

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • The Method — may refer to:* The Method of Mechanical Theorems , a work of Archimedes * The Method, a 1997 musical album by Killing Time * An obscure band of UK/Irish origin, Andwella, which also went by the name The Method * The Method , a song by We Are… …   Wikipedia

  • Method — may refer to: Scientific method, a series of steps taken to acquire knowledge Method (computer programming), a piece of code associated with a class or object to perform a task Method (music), a kind of textbook to help students learning to play… …   Wikipedia

  • Method of exhaustion — This article is about the method of finding the area of a shape using limits. For the method of proof, see Proof by exhaustion. The method of exhaustion (methodus exhaustionibus, or méthode des anciens) is a method of finding the area of a shape… …   Wikipedia

  • On the Sphere and Cylinder — is a work that was published by Archimedes in two volumes c. 225 BC.[1] It most notably details how to find the surface area of a sphere and the volume of the contained ball and the analogous values for a cylinder, and was the first to do so.[2]… …   Wikipedia

  • History of the Church-Turing thesis — This article is an extension of the history of the Church Turing thesis.The debate and discovery of the meaning of computation and recursion has been long and contentious. This article provides detail of that debate and discovery from Peano s… …   Wikipedia

  • History of the Church–Turing thesis — This article is an extension of the history of the Church–Turing thesis. The debate and discovery of the meaning of computation and recursion has been long and contentious. This article provides detail of that debate and discovery from Peano s… …   Wikipedia

  • Science and mathematics from the Renaissance to Descartes — George Molland Early in the nineteenth century John Playfair wrote for the Encyclopaedia Britannica a long article entitled ‘Dissertation; exhibiting a General View of the Progress of Mathematics and Physical Science, since the Revival of Letters …   History of philosophy

  • Logic and the philosophy of mathematics in the nineteenth century — John Stillwell INTRODUCTION In its history of over two thousand years, mathematics has seldom been disturbed by philosophical disputes. Ever since Plato, who is said to have put the slogan ‘Let no one who is not a geometer enter here’ over the… …   History of philosophy

  • Herbert of Cherbury (Lord) and the Cambridge Platonists — Lord Herbert of Cherbury and the Cambridge Platonists Sarah Hutton The philosophy of Lord Herbert of Cherbury (1582/3–1648) and of the Cambridge Platonists exemplifies the continuities of seventeenth century thought with Renaissance philosophy.… …   History of philosophy

  • Scientific method — …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”