Natural Ontological Attitude

Natural Ontological Attitude

Arthur Fine published "The Natural Ontological Attitude"[1] in 1984 and a sequel, "And Not Antirealism Either"[2] in the same year. His subject is the nature and validity of scientific knowledge and his goal is to get the reader to abandon either realism or antirealism as he understands them. In their place he advocates a "natural ontological attitude" (NOA). Both articles were republished as chapters in Fine's book The Shakey Game,[3] which takes its title from a comment by Einstein that physicists who undermine causality in physics are playing a shakey/risky game.

Fine argues that both realists and anti-realists share a basic "core" position about both everyday things and scientific statements. Realists and antirealists both trust the evidence of their senses that tables, chairs and other people are present before us and in some sense exist. They also trust the substantiated pronouncements of science that protons and electrons exist and have the size, mass and charge science assigns them. To quote Fine about such common ("core") positions: "…it is possible to accept the evidence of one's senses and accept, in the same way [his italics], the confirmed results of science…."[4]. Stated another way: "…both realist and antirealist accept the results of scientific investigations as 'true,' on par with more homely [commonplace, everyday] truths."

So if everybody, realist and antirealist included, shares a core position about entities that exist and propositions that are true (e.g., F = ma) where do the differences lie? They lie, according to Fine, in the additions that partisans make to the core. Antirealists may add "the pragmatic…[or] instrumentalist…[or] conventionalist conceptions of truth…[or maybe add an overlay of] idealism, constructivism, phenomenalism [or] empiricism."[5] Spelling out what realists add to the core position takes Fine a long paragraph that boils down to simply one charge: "correspondence with the world … claims about reality."[6]

Fine then goes on. "It seems to me that when we contrast the realist and the antirealist in terms of what they each want to add to the core position, a third alternative emerges—and an attractive one at that. It is the core position itself, and all by itself [his italics]."[7] Fine continues, "…at heart, the grip of realism only extends to the homely connection of everyday truths with scientific truths, and that good sense dictates our acceptance of the one on the same basis as our acceptance of the other, then the homely line makes the core position, all by itself, a compelling one...."[8]

Realism itself is unpalatable to Fine because of the realist's desire to connect truths about an entity (say the mass or charge of an electron) to an actual, existing entity (electron). It is permissible to believe in the properties of an electron but not in the electron itself as the bearer of those properties. That is the mistake realists make. Yet Fine admits that the working scientist believes "…in the existence of those entities to which his theories refer."[9] In addition, Fine concedes that practitioners of science are in no need of the goals, interpretations or justifications of science that theorists can provide.[10] And although scientists may discover more and more properties of, or facts about, an entity, Fine insists that we should not confuse successive advances in our knowledge of an entity with closer approximations as to what that entity actually is.

Antirealists also come under criticism. Theorists who define truth in terms of "acceptance" (rational agreement), or behaviorism or empiricism are all "truthmongers" who are seeking some foundation, some rationale, for what they believe. They make the same basic mistake as the realists since they "rely on metaphysical or epistemological hearing aids"[11] to hear the voice of science. Only NOA is immune from these delusions and distractions. Fine concludes And Not Antirealism Either by arguing that truth is a semantical concept and not an ontological or metaphysical concept. He argues that those who wish to ground "truth" in correspondence, empiricism, pragmatism, acceptance, etc. are all making the same fundamental mistake. Embrace NOA he argues and be non-judgmental and heuristic in your pursuit of knowledge. Reject the concept of "truth" as a gold standard to which all knowledge must be compared or evaluated.

Criticism

Since Fine criticizes both realists and antirealists he has come in for criticism from both sides. Many critics could not resist some word play with NOA/NOAH, ark, and "Fine."[12] Alan Musgrave argues that Fine distorts the varied positions of antirealists especially with regard to their support of the "core."[13] He and others object to the way Fine equates his "core" position with their definition (or anti-definition) of "true." Robert Klee writes: "NOA seems like obvious inconsistent fence-sitting."[14] Richard Schlagel writes "I find it utterly implausible that Fine could be serious when he argues that explanatory success could have nothing at all to do with truth."[15]

References

  1. ^ Scientific Realism, pp. 83-107, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984
  2. ^ Nous 18, pp. 51-65, 1984.
  3. ^ The Shakey Game, pp. 112-50, Univ. of Chicago Press, 1986.
  4. ^ Shakey Game, p. 127,
  5. ^ Shakey Game, pp. 128-29,
  6. ^ Shakey Game, p. 129,
  7. ^ Shakey Game p. 129,
  8. ^ Shakey Game pp. 129-30,
  9. ^ Shakey Game p. 130,
  10. ^ Shakey Game, top of p. 148,
  11. ^ Shakey Game p. 150.
  12. ^ Richard H. Schlagel, "Critical Notice: Fine's 'Shaky Game' (and Why NOA is no Ark for Science)", Philosophy of Science, Vol. 58, No. 2, June, 1991, pp. 307-323. Also the Musgrave article below.
  13. ^ Alan Musgrave, "NOA'S Ark -- Fine for Realism," The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 39 No. 157, pp. 383-98.
  14. ^ Introduction to the Philosophy of Science: Cutting Nature at Its Seams p. 238, Oxford University Press, 1997.
  15. ^ Quoted in Cutting Nature at Its Seams, p. 238.

External links


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно сделать НИР?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • science, philosophy of — Branch of philosophy that attempts to elucidate the nature of scientific inquiry observational procedures, patterns of argument, methods of representation and calculation, metaphysical presuppositions and evaluate the grounds of their validity… …   Universalium

  • Verificationism — is the view that a statement or question is only legitimate if there is some way to determine whether the statement is true or false, or what the answer to the question is. It is a view mostly closely associated with the logical positivists of… …   Wikipedia

  • Pragmatism — This article is about the philosophical movement. For other uses, see Pragmatism (disambiguation). Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition centered on the linking of practice and theory. It describes a process where theory is extracted from… …   Wikipedia

  • Arthur Fine — Infobox Philosopher region = Western Philosophy era = 20th century philosophy color = #B0C4DE |image caption = name = Arthur Fine birth = 1937 death = school tradition = Analytic main interests = Philosophy of science Pragmatism· Quantum… …   Wikipedia

  • Noa — may refer to: Contents 1 Name 2 People 3 Characters 4 Places 5 Concepts …   Wikipedia

  • Judaism — /jooh dee iz euhm, day , deuh /, n. 1. the monotheistic religion of the Jews, having its ethical, ceremonial, and legal foundation in the precepts of the Old Testament and in the teachings and commentaries of the rabbis as found chiefly in the… …   Universalium

  • Phenomenology (The beginnings of) — The beginnings of phenomenology Husserl and his predecessors Richard Cobb Stevens Edmund Husserl was the founder of phenomenology, one of the principal movements of twentieth century philosophy. His principal contribution to philosophy was his… …   History of philosophy

  • metaphysics — /met euh fiz iks/, n. (used with a sing. v.) 1. the branch of philosophy that treats of first principles, includes ontology and cosmology, and is intimately connected with epistemology. 2. philosophy, esp. in its more abstruse branches. 3. the… …   Universalium

  • Christianity — /kris chee an i tee/, n., pl. Christianities. 1. the Christian religion, including the Catholic, Protestant, and Eastern Orthodox churches. 2. Christian beliefs or practices; Christian quality or character: Christianity mixed with pagan elements; …   Universalium

  • Hermeneutics — Gadamer and Ricoeur G.B.Madison THE HISTORICAL BACKGROUND: ROMANTIC HERMENEUTICS Although the term ‘hermeneutics’ (hermeneutica) is, in its current usage, of early modern origin,1 the practice it refers to is as old as western civilization itself …   History of philosophy

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”