Sextus Empiricus

Sextus Empiricus

Infobox Philosopher
region = Western Philosophy
era = Ancient philosophy
color = #B0C4DE


name = Sextus Empiricus
birth = c. 160 AD
death = c. 210 AD, possibly in Alexandria or Rome
school_tradition = Skepticism
influences = Pyrrho, Timon of Phlius, Arcesilaus, Carneades, Aenesidemus, Agrippa, Herodotus of Tarsus
influenced = Michel de Montaigne, Descartes, David Hume, Edmund Husserl and Hegel

Sextus Empiricus (c. 160-210 AD), was a physician and philosopher, and has been variously reported to have lived in Alexandria, Rome, or Athens. His philosophical work is the most complete surviving account of ancient Greek and Roman skepticism.

In his medical work, tradition maintains that he belonged to the "empiric" school (see Asclepiades), as reflected by his name. However, at least twice in his writings, Sextus seems to place himself closer to the "methodic" school, as his philosophical views imply.

Writings

Sextus Empiricus's three known works are the "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" (Πυῤῥώνειοι ὑποτύπωσεις or "Pyrrhōneioi hypotypōseis"), and two distinct works preserved under the same title, "Against the Mathematicians" ("Adversus Mathematicos"), one of which is probably incomplete.

The first six books of "Against the Mathematicians" are commonly known as "Against the Professors", but each book also has a traditional title ("Against the Grammarians" (book I), "Against the Rhetoricians" (book II), "Against the Geometricians" (book III), "Against the Arithmeticians" (book IV), "Against the Astrologers" (book V), "Against the Musicians" (book VI)). It is widely believed that this is Sextus's latest and most mature work.

Books VII-XI of "Against the Mathematicians" form an incomplete whole; scholars believe that at least one, but possibly as many as five books, are missing from the beginning of the work. The extant books have the traditional titles "Against the Logicians" (books VII-VIII), "Against the Physicists" (books IX-X,) and "Against the Ethicists" (book XI). "Against the Mathematicians" VII-XI is sometimes distinguished from "Against the Mathematicians" I-VI by giving it the title "Against the Dogmatists" (in which case "Against the Logicians" are called books I-II, "Against the Physicists" are called books III-IV, and "Against the Ethicists" is called book V, despite the fact that it is commonly believed that the beginning of the work is missing and it is not known how many books might have preceded the extant books).

Note that none of these titles except "Adversus Mathematicos" ("Against the Mathematicians") and Πυῤῥώνειοι ὑποτύπωσεις ("Outlines of Pyrrhonism"), are found in the manuscripts.

Philosophy

Sextus Empiricus raised concerns which applied to all types of knowledge. He doubted the validity of induction [Sextus Empiricus. "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" trans. R.G. Bury (Loeb edn) (London: W. Heinemann, 1933), p. 283.] long before its most well known critic David Hume, and raised the regress argument against all forms of reasoning:

Because of these and other barriers to acquiring true beliefs, Sextus Empiricus advises [The extent to which a skeptic can hold beliefs as well as the kinds of beliefs a skeptic can have is a matter of scholarly dispute.] that we should suspend judgment about virtually all beliefs, that is, we should neither affirm any belief as true nor deny any belief as false. This view is known as Pyrrhonian skepticism, as distinguished from Academic skepticism, as practised by Carneades, which, according to Sextus, denies knowledge altogether. Sextus did not deny the possibility of knowledge. He criticizes the Academic skeptic's claim that nothing is knowable as being an affirmative belief. Instead, Sextus advocates simply giving up belief: that is, suspending judgment about whether or not anything is knowable. [See "PH" I.3, I.8, I.198; cf. J. Barnes, "Introduction", xix ff., in Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Scepticism". Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes (transl.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).] Only by suspending judgment can we attain a state of ataraxia (roughly, 'peace of mind'). Sextus did not think such a general suspension of judgment to be impractical, since we may live without any beliefs, acting by habit.

Sextus allowed that we might affirm claims about our experience (e.g., reports about our feelings or sensations). That is, for some claim X that I feel or perceive, it could be true to say "it seems to me now that X." However, he pointed out that this does not imply any objective knowledge of external reality. For while I might know that the honey I eat tastes sweet to me, this is merely a subjective judgment, and as such may not tell me anything true about the honey itself.

Sextus severely criticised the Stoics throughout his work, especially the Stoic view that signs can indirectly reveal something about the non-evident. [e.g. Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Translated by R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.213-237]

Interpretations of Sextus's philosophy along the above lines have been advocated by scholars such as Myles Burnyeat, [Burnyeat, M., "Can The Sceptic Live His Scepticism" in Myles Burnyeat and Michael Frede (ed.), "The Original Sceptics: A Controversy" (Hackett, 1997): 25-57. Cf. Burnyeat, M., "The Sceptic in His Place and Time", "ibid.", 92-126.] Jonathan Barnes, [Barnes, J., "The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist" in Myles Burnyeat and Michael Frede (ed.), "The Original Sceptics: A Controversy" (Hackett, 1997): 58-91.] and Benson Mates. [Mates, B. "The Skeptic Way" (Oxford UP, 1996).]

Michael Frede, however, defends a different interpretation, [Frede, M., "The Sceptic's Beliefs" in Myles Burnyeat and Michael Frede (ed.), "The Original Sceptics: A Controversy" (Hackett, 1997): 1-24. Cf. Frede, M., "The Sceptic's Two Kinds of Assent and the Question of the Possibility of Knowledge", "ibid.", 127-152.] according to which Sextus does allow beliefs, so long as they are not derived by reason, philosophy or speculation; a skeptic may, for example, accept common opinions in the skeptic's society. However, the content of such beliefs is purely conventional or subjective. Thus, on this interpretation, the skeptic may well entertain the belief that God does or does not exist or that virtue is good. But he may not believe that such claims are true by nature.

The Ten Modes of Pyrrhonism

Pyrrhonism is more a mental attitude or therapy as opposed to a theory. It involves setting things in opposition and owing to the equipollence of the objects and reasons, one suspends judgement. "We oppose either appearances to appearances or objects of thought to objects of thought or "alternando." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 23] The ten modes induce suspension of judgement and in turn a state of mental suspense followed by ataraxia. If ever one is in a position in which they are unable to refute a theory, Pyrrhonists reply "Just as, before the birth of the founder of the School to which you belong, the theory it holds was not as yet apparent as a sound theory, although it was really in existence, so likewise it is possible that the opposite theory to that which you now propound is already really existent, though not yet apparent to us, so that we ought not as yet to yield assent to this theory which at the moment seems to be valid." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Translated by R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 23] These ten "modes" or "tropes" were originally listed by Aenesidemus.

# "The same impressions are not produced by the same objects owing to the differences in animals." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 27]
# "The same impressions are not produced by the same objects owing to the differences among human beings." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 47]
# "The same impressions are not produced by the same objects owing to the differences among the senses." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 55]
# "Owing to the "circumstances, conditions or dispositions." For example drunk as opposed to sober, sick as opposed to well, etc. [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.61]
# "Based on positions, distances, and locations; for owing to each of these the same objects appear different;" The same tower appears rectangular at close distance and round from far away. [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.69]
# "“we deduce that since no object strikes us entirely by itself, but along with something else, it may perhaps be possible to say what the mixture compounded out of the external object and the thing perceived with it is like, but we would not be able to say what the external object is like by itself…" [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.73]
# "...based, as we said, on the quantity and constitution of the underlying objects, meaning generally by "constitution" the manner of composition." Goat horn appears black when intact and appears white when ground up. [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.77]
# "“…since all things appear relative, we will suspend judgement about what things exist absolutely and really existent." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 79] "Do things which exist "differentially" or "have a distinct existence of their own" differ from relative things or not? If they do not differ, then they too are relative; but if they differ, then, since everything which differs is relative to something..., things which exist differentially are relative." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p.81]
# "Based on constancy or rarity of occurrence." The sun is more amazing than a comet, but because we see the sun daily and the comet rarely, the latter commands our attention. [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 83]
# "...mainly concerned with Ethics, being based on rules of conduct, habits, laws, legendary beliefs, and dogmatic conceptions." [Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism", Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 85]

Legacy

An influential Latin translation of Sextus's "Outlines" was published by Henricus Stephanus in Geneva in 1562, and this was followed by a complete Latin Sextus with Gentian Hervet as translator in 1569. [Richard Popkin (editor), "History of Western Philosophy" (1998) p. 330.] Petrus and Jacobus Chouet published the Greek text for the first time in 1621. Stephanus did not publish it with his Latin translation either in 1562 or in 1569, nor was it published in the reprint of the latter in 1619.Sextus's "Outlines" were widely read in Europe during the 16th, 17th and 18th centuries, and had a profound impact on Michel de Montaigne, David Hume, and G.W.F. Hegel, among many others. Another source for the circulation of Sextus's ideas was Bayle's "Dictionary". The legacy of Pyrrhonism is described in Richard Popkin's "The History of Skepticism from Erasmus to Descartes" and "High Road to Pyrrhonism". The transmission of Sextus's manuscripts through antiquity and the Middle Ages is reconstructed by Luciano Floridi's [http://www.us.oup.com/us/catalog/general/subject/ClassicalStudies/AncientPhilosophy/?view=usa&ci=9780195146714 "Sextus Empiricus, The Recovery and Transmission of Pyrrhonism"] . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

See also

* Pyrrhonism
* Problem of induction
* Philosophical skepticism
* Skepticism
* Phenomenology (philosophy)

Notes

References

Translations


*Sextus Empiricus, "Against the Grammarians (Adversos Mathematicos I)". David Blank (trans.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998). ISBN 0-19-824470-3.
*Sextus Empiricus, "Against the Ethicists: (Adversus Mathematicos XI)". Richard Bett (trans.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000). ISBN 0-19-825097-5
*Sextus Empiricus, "Against the Logicians". Richard Bett (trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). ISBN 0-521-53195-0
*Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Scepticism". Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes (trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed. 2000). ISBN 0-521-77809-3
*Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism". R.G. Bury (trans.) (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1990). ISBN 0-87975-597-0
*Sextus Empiricus, "Selections from the Major Writings on Skepticism Man and God". Sanford G. Etheridge (trans.) (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985). ISBN 0-87220-006-X
*Sextus Empiricus, "Sextus Empiricus I: Outlines of Pyrrhonism". R.G. Bury (trans.) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1933/2000). ISBN 0-674-99301-2
*Sextus Empiricus, "Sextus Empiricus II: Against the Logicians". R.G. Bury (trans.) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1935/1997). ISBN 0-674-99321-7
*Sextus Empiricus, "Sextus Empiricus III: Against the Physicists, Against The Ethicists". R.G. Bury (trans.) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1936/1997). ISBN 0-674-99344-6
*Sextus Empiricus, "Sextus Empiricus IV: Against the Professors". R.G. Bury (trans.) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1949/2000). ISBN 0-674-99420-5
*Sextus Empiricus, "The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus's Outlines of Pyrrhonism". Benson Mates (trans.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996). ISBN 0-19-509213-9

*", hoc est, adversus eos qui profitentur disciplinas", Gentiano Herveto Aurelio interprete, Parisiis, M. Javenem, 1569 (Vicifons).

Scholarly works


*Annas, Julia and Barnes, Jonathan, "The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations" (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). ISBN 0-521-27644-6
*Bett, Richard, "Pyrrho, his antecedents, and his legacy" (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). ISBN 0-19-925661-6
*Brennan, Tad, "Ethics and Epistemology in Sextus Empiricus" (London: Garland, 1999). ISBN 0815336594
*Brochard, "Les Sceptiques grecs" (1887)
*Burnyeat, Myles & Frede, Michael "The Original Sceptics: A Controversy" (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997). ISBN 0-87220-347-6
*Hankinson, R.J., "The Skeptics" (London: Routledge, 1998). ISBN 0-415-18446-0
*Jourdain, "Sextus Empiricus" (Paris, 1858)
*Mates, Benson. "The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus's Outlines of Pyrrhonism." (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
*Pappenheim, "Lebensverholtnisse des Sextus Empiricus" (Berlin, 1875)
*Popkin, Richard, "The History of Scepticism: From Savonarola to Bayle" (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003). ISBN 0-19-510768-3

----


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Sextus Empiricus — (griechisch Σέξτος Ἐμπειρικός, Sextos Empeirikós) war ein Arzt und Philosoph im 2. Jahrhundert n. Chr., der mehrere Werke in griechischer Sprache verfasst hat. Sextus Empiricus war ein Vertreter des Pyrrhonismus …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Sextus Empiricus — est un philosophe, astronome et médecin sceptique empirique qui fut actif vers 190. Il était grec, mais nous ne savons ni où il naquit (peut être à Mytilène) ni où il fut professeur. Nous savons en revanche qu il fut chef de l école… …   Wikipédia en Français

  • SEXTUS EMPIRICUS — (2e moitié IIe déb. IIIe s.) Du philosophe sceptique grec Sextus Empiricus on possède trois grandes œuvres: les Hypotyposes pyrrhoniennes en six livres; le traité Contre les professeurs (Adversus mathematicos ) en trois livres (contre les… …   Encyclopédie Universelle

  • Sextus Empirĭcus — Sextus Empirĭcus, griech. Philosoph und Arzt, lebte um 200 n. Chr. in Alexandria und Athen, gehörte als Philosoph der skeptischen Richtung an, wurde aber als Arzt den Empirikern beigezählt. Wir haben von ihm noch zwei wertvolle Schriften:… …   Meyers Großes Konversations-Lexikon

  • Sextus Empiricus — Sextus Empiricus, griech. Philosoph um 200 v. Chr., Empiricus genannt, weil er als Arzt zu der Schule der Empiriker (s. d.) gehalten haben soll, ist der wichtigste unter den Skeptikern der spätern Zeit. Ein Werk in 3 Büchern richtete er gegen… …   Herders Conversations-Lexikon

  • Sextus Empiricus — Sextus Empirĭcus, griech. skeptischer Philosoph und Arzt zu Ende des 2. Jahrh. n. Chr. in Alexandria und Rom. Schriften hg. von Bekker (1842), deutsch z. T. von Pappenheim (1877) …   Kleines Konversations-Lexikon

  • SEXTUS EMPIRICUS° — (late second century C.E.), Greek physician and philosophical writer in whose works on Skepticism (extant) the Jewish abhorrence of pig s flesh is mentioned (Pyrrhonic Sketches 3:223) …   Encyclopedia of Judaism

  • Sextus Empiricus — Sẹxtus Empiricus,   griechischer Philosoph und Arzt des 2./3. Jahrhunderts n. Chr. Der Ort seines Wirkens ist nicht bekannt. Der Beiname »Empiricus« beruht vermutlich auf einer Zuweisung zur »empirischen« Ärzteschule. Sextus Empiricus stützt… …   Universal-Lexikon

  • Sextus Empiricus — (fl. c. AD 200) Doctor of medicine, and author of the most distinguished works of ancient scepticism that have survived. Sextus was a Greek who may have spent time in Rome, and Alexandria, but little is known about his life, including where he… …   Philosophy dictionary

  • Sextus Empiricus — ▪ Greek philosopher flourished 3rd century       ancient Greek philosopher historian who produced the only extant comprehensive account of Greek Skepticism in his Outlines of Pyrrhonism and Against the Dogmatists.       As a major exponent of… …   Universalium

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”