Second-order arithmetic

Second-order arithmetic

In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and sets thereof. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics. The standard axiomatization of second-order arithmetic is denoted Z2.

Second-order arithmetic includes, but is significantly stronger than, its first-order counterpart Peano arithmetic. Unlike Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic allows quantification over sets of numbers as well as numbers themselves. Because real numbers can be represented as (infinite) sets of natural numbers in well-known ways, and because second order arithmetic allows quantification over such sets, it is possible to formalize the real numbers in second-order arithmetic. For this reason, second-order arithmetic is sometimes called “analysis”.

Second-order arithmetic can also be seen as a weak version of set theory in which the set elements are either natural numbers or sets of natural numbers. Although much weaker than Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, second-order arithmetic can prove essentially all of results of classical mathematics expressible in its language.

A subsystem of second-order arithmetic is a theory in the language of second-order arithmetic each axiom of which is a theorem of full second-order arithmetic (Z2). Such subsystems are essential to reverse mathematics, a research program investigating how much of classical mathematics can be derived in certain weak subsystems of varying strength. Much of core mathematics can be formalized in these weak subsystems, some of which are defined below. Reverse mathematics also clarifies the extent and manner in which classical mathematics is nonconstructive.

Definitional

yntax

The language of second-order arithmetic is two-sorted. The first sort of terms and variables, usually denoted by lower case letters, consists of individuals, whose intended interpretation is as natural numbers. The other sort of variables, variously called “set variables,” “class variables,” or even “predicates” are usually denoted by upper case letters. They refer to classes/predicates/properties of individuals, and so can be thought of as sets of natural numbers. Both individuals and set variables can be quantified universally or existentially. A formula which has no bound set variables (that is, no quantifiers over set variables) is called arithmetical. An arithmetical formula may have free set variables and bound individual variables.

Individual terms are formed from the constant 0, the unary function "S" (the "successor function"), and the binary operations + and · (addition and multiplication). The successor function adds 1 (="S"0) to its input. The relations = (equality) and < (comparison of natural numbers) relate two individuals, whereas the relation &isin; (membership) relates an individual and a set (or class).

For example forall n (nin X ightarrow Sn in X) is a well-formed formula of second-order arithmetic which is arithmetical, which has one free set variable "X" and one bound individual variable "n" (but no bound set variables, as is required of an arithmetical formula), whereas exists X forall n(nin X leftrightarrow n < SSSSSS0cdot SSSSSSS0) is a well-formed formula which is not arithmetical with one bound set variable "X" and one bound individual variable "n".

emantics

Several different interpretations of the quantifiers are possible. If second-order arithmetic is studied using the full semantics of second-order logic then the set quantifiers range over all subsets of the range of the number variables. If second-order arithmetic is formalized using the semantics of first-order logic then any model includes a domain for the set variables to range over, and this domain may be a proper subset of the full powerset of the domain of number variables.

Although second-order arithmetic was originally studied using full second-order semantics, the vast majority of current research treats second-order arithmetic in first-order predicate calculus. This is because the model theory of subsystems of second-order arithmetic is more interesting in the setting of first-order logic.

Axioms

Basic

The following axioms are known as the "basic axioms", or sometimes the "Robinson axioms." The first-order system they define, known as Robinson arithmetic, is essentially Peano arithmetic without induction.

* forall m (Sm=0 ightarrow ot) (“the successor of a natural number is never zero”)
* forall m forall n (Sm=Sn ightarrow m=n) (“the successor function is injective”)
* forall n (0=n lor exists m (Sm=n)) (“every natural number is zero or a successor”)
* forall m (m+0=m)
* forall m forall n (m+Sn = S(m+n))
* forall m (mcdot 0 = 0)
* forall m forall n (m cdot Sn = (mcdot n)+m)
* forall m (m<0 ightarrow ot) (“no natural number is smaller than zero”)
* forall m (m
* forall n (0=n lor 0 (“every natural number is zero or bigger than zero”)
* forall m forall n ((Sm

Note that all these axioms are first order (that is involve no set variables at all, something even stronger than being arithmetical). The first three, together with mathematical induction, form the usual Peano axioms (the third, actually, is a consequence of even the weakest induction schemes), whereas the subsequent axioms are a definition of addition, multiplication and order on the natural numbers (again, the last two are redundant as soon as any kind of induction axiom is added).

Induction and comprehension schema

If φ("n") is a formula of second-order arithmetic with a free number variable "n" and possible other free number or set variables (written "m" and "X"), the induction axiom for φ is the axiom:

:forall m_ullet forall X_ullet ((varphi(0) land forall n (varphi(n) ightarrow varphi(Sn)) ightarrow forall n varphi(n))

The (full) second-order induction scheme consists of all instances of this axiom, over all second-order formulas.

One particularly important instance of the induction scheme is when φ is the formula “n in X” expressing the fact that "n" is a member of "X" ("X" being a free set variable): in this case, the induction axiom for φ is

:forall X ((0in X land forall n (nin X ightarrow Snin X)) ightarrow forall n (nin X))

This sentence is called the second-order induction axiom.

Returning to the case where φ("n") is a formula with a free variable "n" and possibly other free variables, we define the comprehension axiom for φ to be:

:forall m_ullet forall X_ullet exists Z forall n (nin Z leftrightarrow varphi(n))

Essentially, this allows us to form the set Z = { n | varphi(n) } of natural numbers satisfying φ("n"). There is a technical restriction that the formula φ may not contain the variable "Z", for otherwise the formula n ot in Z would lead to the comprehension axiom:exists Z forall n ( n in Z leftrightarrow n ot in Z)which is inconsistent. This convention is assumed in the remainder of this article.

The full system

The formal theory of second-order arithmetic (in the language of second-order arithmetic) consists of the basic axioms, the comprehension axiom for every formula φ, (arithmetic or otherwise) and the second-order induction axiom. This theory is sometimes called "full second order arithmetic" to distinguish it from its subsystems, defined below. Second-order semantics eliminates the need for the comprehension axiom, because these semantics imply that every possible set exists.

In the presence of the unrestricted comprehension scheme, the single second-order induction axiom implies each instance of the full induction scheme. Those subsystems, described below, which limit comprehension in some way may offset this limitation by including part of the induction scheme.

Models of second-order arithmetic

Recall that we view second-order arithmetic as a theory in first-order predicate calculus. Thus a model mathcal{M} of the language of second-order arithmetic consists of a set "M" (which forms the range of individual variables) together with a constant 0 (an element of "M"), a function "S" from "M" to "M", two binary operations + and · on "M", a binary relation < on "M", and a collection "D" of subsets of "M" which is the range of the set variables. By omitting "D" we obtain a model of the language of first order arithmetic.

When "D" is the full powerset of "M", the model mathcal{M} is called a full model. The use of full second-order semantics is equivalent to limiting the models of second-order arithmetic to the full models. In fact, the axioms of second-order arithmetic have only one full model. This follows from the fact that the axioms of Peano arithmetic with the second-order induction axiom have only one model under second-order semantics.

When "M" is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual operations, mathcal{M} is called an ω-model. In this case we may identify the model with "D", its collection of sets of naturals, because this set is enough to completely determine an ω-model.

The unique full model, which is the usual set of natural numbers with its usual structure and all its subsets, is called the intended or standard model of second-order arithmetic.

ubsystems of second-order arithmetic

There are many named subsystems of second-order arithmetic.

A subscript 0 in the name of a subsystem indicates that it includes onlya restricted portion of the full second-order induction scheme (Friedman 1976). Such a restriction lowers the proof-theoretic strength of the system significantly. For example, the system ACA0 described below is equiconsistent with Peano arithmetic. The corresponding theory ACA, consisting of ACA0 plus the full second-order induction scheme, is stronger than Peano arithmetic.

Arithmetical comprehension

Many of the well-studied subsystems are related to closure properties of models. For example, it can be shown that every ω-model of full second-order arithmetic is closed under Turing jump, but not every ω-model closed under Turing jump is a model of full second-order arithmetic. We may ask whether there is a subsystem of second-order arithmetic which is satisfied by every ω-model that is closed under Turing jump and satisfies some other, more mild, closure conditions. The subsystem just described is called mathrm{ACA}_0.

mathrm{ACA}_0 is defined as the theory consisting of the basic axioms, the arithmetical comprehension axiom scheme, in other words the comprehension axiom for every "arithmetical" formula φ, and the ordinary second-order induction axiom; again, we could also choose to include the arithmetical induction axiom scheme, in other words the induction axiom for every arithmetical formula φ, without making a difference.

It can be seen that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of mathrm{ACA}_0 if and only if S is closed under Turing jump, Turing reducibility, and Turing join.

The subscript 0 in mathrm{ACA}_0 indicates that we have not included every instance of the induction axiom in this subsystem. This makes no difference when we study only ω-models, which automatically satisfy every instance of the induction axiom. It is of crucial importance, however, when we study models that are not ω-models. The system consisting of mathrm{ACA}_0 plus induction for all formulas is sometimes called mathrm{ACA}.

The system mathrm{ACA}_0 is a conservative extension of first-order arithmetic (or first-order Peano axioms), defined as the basic axioms, plus the first order induction axiom scheme (for all formulas φ involving no class variables at all, bound or otherwise), in the language of first order arithmetic (which does not permit class variables at all). In particular it has the same proof-theoretic ordinal ε0 as first-order arithmetic, owing to the limited induction schema.

The arithmetical hierarchy for formulas

To define a second subsystem, we will need a bit more terminology.

A formula is called "bounded arithmetical", or Δ00, when all its quantifiers are of the form ∀"n"<"t" or ∃"n"<"t" (where "n" is the individual variable being quantified and "t" is an individual term), where

:forall n

stands for

:forall n(n

and

:exists n

stands for

:exists n(n.

A formula is called Σ01 (or sometimes Σ1), respectively Π01 (or sometimes Π1) when it of the form ∃"m"(φ), respectively ∀"m"(φ) where φ is a bounded arithmetical formula and "m" is an individual variable (that is free in φ). More generally, a formula is called Σ0"n", respectively Π0"n" when it is obtained by adding existential, respectively universal, individual quantifiers to a Π0"n"−1, respectively Σ0"n"−1 formula (and Σ00 and Π00 are all equivalent to Δ00). Note that by construction all these formulas are arithmetical (no class variables are ever bound) and, in fact, by putting the formula in Skolem prenex form one can see that every arithmetical formula is equivalent to a Σ0"n" or Π0"n" formula for all large enough "n".

Recursive Comprehension

The subsystem mathrm{RCA}_0 is an even weaker system than mathrm{ACA}_o and is often used as the base system in Reverse Mathematics. It consists of: the basic axioms, the Σ01 induction scheme, and the Δ01 comprehension scheme. The former term is clear: the Σ01 induction scheme is the induction axiom for every Σ01 formula φ. The term “Δ01 comprehension” requires a little more explaining, however: there is no such thing as a Δ01 formula (the "intended" meaning is a formula which is both Σ01 and Π01), but we are instead postulating the comprehension axiom for every Σ01 formula "subject to the condition" that it is equivalent to a Π01 formula, in other words, for every Σ01 formula φ and every Π01 formula ψ we postulate

:forall m_ullet forall X_ullet ((forall n (varphi(n) leftrightarrow psi(n))) ightarrow exists Z forall n (nin Z leftrightarrow varphi(n)))

mathrm{RCA}_0 is a conservative extension of Peano arithmetic with induction restricted to Σ01 formulas, and has proof theoretic ordinal ωω (because of the limited induction).

It can be seen that a collection S of subsets of ω determines an ω-model of mathrm{RCA}_0if and only if S is closed under Turing reducibility and Turing join. In particular, the collection of all computable subsets of ω gives an ω-model of mathrm{RCA}_0. This is the motivation behind the name of this system --- if a set can be proved to exist using mathrm{RCA}_0, then the set is computable (i.e. recursive).

Weaker systems

Sometimes an even weaker system than mathrm{RCA}_0 is desired. One such system is defined as follows: one must first augment the language of arithmetic with an exponential function (in stronger systems the exponential can be defined in terms of addition and multiplication by the usual trick, but when the system becomes too weak this is no longer possible) and the basic axioms by the obvious axioms defining exponentiation inductively from multiplication; then the system consists of the (enriched) basic axioms, plus Δ01 comprehension plus Δ00 induction.

tronger systems

Much as we have defined Σ"n" and Π"n" (or, more accurately, Σ0"n" and Π0"n") formulae, we can define Σ1"n" and Π1"n" formulae in the following way: a Δ10 (or Σ10 or Π10) formula is just an arithmetical formula, and a Σ1"n", respectively Π1"n", formula is obtained by adding existential, respectively universal, class quantifiers in front of a Π1"n"−1, respectively Σ1"n"−1.

It is not too hard to see that over a not too weak system, any formula of second-order arithmetic is equivalent to a Σ1"n" or Π1"n" formula for all large enough "n". The system Π11-comprehension is the system consisting of the basic axioms, plus the ordinary second-order induction axiom and the comprehension axiom for every Π11 formula φ. It is an easy exercise to show that this is actually equivalent to Σ11-comprehension (on the other hand, Δ11-comprehension, defined by the same trick as introduced earlier for Δ01 comprehension, is actually weaker).

Coding mathematics in second-order arithmetic

Second-order arithmetic allows us to speak directly (without coding) of natural numbers and sets of natural numbers. Pairs of natural numbers can be coded in the usual way as natural numbers, so arbitrary integers or rational numbers are first-class citizens in the same manner as natural numbers. Functions between these sets can be encoded as sets of pairs, and hence as subsets of the natural numbers, without difficulty. Real numbers can be defined as Cauchy sequences of rational numbers, but for technical reasons not discussed here, it is preferable (in the weak axiom systems above) to constrain the convergence rate (say by requiring that the distance between the "n"-th and ("n"+1)-th term be less than 2−"n"). These systems cannot speak of real functions, or subsets of the reals. Nevertheless, continuous real functions are legitimate objects of study, since they are defined by their values on the rationals. Moreover, a related trick makes it possible to speak of open subsets of the reals. Even Borel sets of reals can be coded in the language of second-order arithmetic, although doing so is a bit tricky.

ee also

*Paris-Harrington theorem
*Reverse mathematics
*Presburger arithmetic
*Peano arithmetic
*Robinson arithmetic
*Second order logic

References

*Burgess, John P., 2005. "Fixing Frege". Princeton University Press.
*Buss, S. R., "Handbook of proof theory" ISBN 0-444-89840-9
*Friedman, Harvey. "Systems of second order arithmetic with restricted induction," I, II (Abstracts). "Journal of Symbolic Logic", v.41, pp. 557-- 559, 1976. [http://www.jstor.org/stable/2272259 JStor]
*Simpson, Stephen G. (1999) " [http://www.math.psu.edu/simpson/sosoa/ Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic,] Perspectives in Mathematical Logic". Berlin: Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-64882-8.
*Gaisi Takeuti (1975) "Proof theory" ISBN 0-444-10492-5


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужно решить контрольную?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Second-order logic — In logic and mathematics second order logic is an extension of first order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic.[1] Second order logic is in turn extended by higher order logic and type theory. First order logic uses only… …   Wikipedia

  • Arithmetic — tables for children, Lausanne, 1835 Arithmetic or arithmetics (from the Greek word ἀριθμός, arithmos “number”) is the oldest and most elementary branch of mathematics, used b …   Wikipedia

  • Order (mathematics) — Contents 1 In algebra 2 In arithmetic 3 In analysis 4 …   Wikipedia

  • First-order logic — is a formal logical system used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. It goes by many names, including: first order predicate calculus, the lower predicate calculus, quantification theory, and predicate logic (a less… …   Wikipedia

  • List of first-order theories — In mathematical logic, a first order theory is given by a set of axioms in somelanguage. This entry lists some of the more common examples used in model theory and some of their properties. PreliminariesFor every natural mathematical structure… …   Wikipedia

  • Robinson arithmetic — In mathematics, Robinson arithmetic, or Q, is a finitely axiomatized fragment of Peano arithmetic (PA), first set out in Robinson (1950). Q is essentially PA without the axiom schema of induction. Even though Q is much weaker than PA, it is still …   Wikipedia

  • Primitive recursive arithmetic — Primitive recursive arithmetic, or PRA, is a quantifier free formalization of the natural numbers. It was first proposed by Skolem [Thoralf Skolem (1923) The foundations of elementary arithmetic in Jean van Heijenoort, translator and ed. (1967)… …   Wikipedia

  • Arithmetic logic unit — schematic symbol Cascadable 8 …   Wikipedia

  • Arithmetic coding — is a method for lossless data compression. Normally, a string of characters such as the words hello there is represented using a fixed number of bits per character, as in the ASCII code. Like Huffman coding, arithmetic coding is a form of… …   Wikipedia

  • arithmetic — arithmetically, adv. n. /euh rith meuh tik/; adj. /ar ith met ik/, n. 1. the method or process of computation with figures: the most elementary branch of mathematics. 2. Also called higher arithmetic, theoretical arithmetic. the theory of… …   Universalium

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”