McCarthy Formalism

McCarthy Formalism

In computer science and recursion theory the McCarthy Formalism (1963) of computer scientist John McCarthy clarifies the notion of recursive functions by use of the IF-THEN-ELSE construction common to computer science, together with the four of the operators of primitive recursive functions: zero, successor, equality of numbers and composition. The conditional operator replaces both primitive recursion and the mu-operator.

Contents

Introduction

McCarthy's notion of conditional expression

McCarthy (1960)[1] described his formalism this way:

"In this article, we first describe a formalism for defining recursively. We believe this formalism has advantages both as a programming language and as a vehicle for developing a theory of computation....
" We shall need a number of mathematical ideas and notations concerning functions in general. Most of the ideas are well known, but the notion of conditional expression is believed to be new, and the use of conditional expressions permits functions to be defined recursively in a new and convenient way."

Minsky's explanation of the "formalism"

In his 1967 Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Marvin Minsky in his §10.6 Conditional Expressions: The McCarthy Formalism describes the "formalism" as follows:

"Practical computer languages do not lend themselves to formal mathematical treatment--they are not designed to make it easy to prove theorems about the procedures they describe. In a paper by McCarthy [1963] we find a formalism that enhances the practical aspect of the recursive-function concept, while preserving and improving its mathematical clarity. ¶ McCarthy introduces "conditional expressions" of the form
f = (if p1 then e1 else e2)
where the ei are expressions and p1 is a statement (or equation) that may be true or false. ¶ This expression means
See if p1 is true; if so the value of f is given by e1.
IF p1 is false, the value of f is given by e2.
This conditional expression . . . has also the power of the minimization operator. . ..
The McCarthy formalism is like the general recursive (Kleene) system, in being based on some basic functions, composition, and equality, but with the conditional expression alone replacing both the primitive-recursive scheme and the minimization operator." (Minsky 1967:192-193)

Minsky uses the following operators in his demonstrations[2]:

  • Zero
  • Successor
  • Equality of numbers
  • Composition (substitution, replacement, assignment)[3]
  • Conditional expression

From these he shows how to derive the predecessor function (i.e. DECREMENT); with this tool he derives the minimization operator necessary for "general" recursion, as well as primitive-recursive definitions.

Expansion of IF-THEN-ELSE to the CASE operator

In his 1952 Introduction of Meta-Mathematics Stephen Kleene provides a definition of what it means to be a primitive recursive function:

"A function φ is primitive recursive in ψ1, ...,ψl (briefly Ψ), if there is a finite sequence φ1, ...,φk of (occurrences of) functions ... such that each function of the sequence is either one of the functions Ψ (the assumed functions), or an initial function, or an immediate dependent of preceding functions, and the last function φk is φ." (Kleene 1952:224)

In other words, given a "basis" function (it can be a constant such as 0), primitive recursion uses either the base or the previous value of the function to produce the value of the function; primitive recursion is sometimes called mathematical induction

Minsky (above) is describing a two-CASE operator. A demonstration that the nested IF-THEN-ELSE—the "case statement" (or "switch statement")--is primitive recursive can be found in Kleene 1952:229[4] at "#F ('mutually-exclusive predicates')". The CASE operator behaves like a logical multiplexer and is simply an extension of the simpler two-case logical operator sometimes called AND-OR-SELECT (see more at Propositional formula). The CASE operator for three cases would be verbally described as: "If X is CASE 1 then DO "p" else if X is CASE 2 then do "q" else if X is CASE "3" then do "r" else do "default".

Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey 2002 observe that in a particular instance the CASE operator, or a sequence of nested IF-THEN-ELSE statements, must be both mutually exclusive, meaning that only one "case" holds (is true), and collectively exhaustive, meaning every possible situation or "case" is "covered". These requirements are a consequence of the determinacy of Propositional logic; the correct implementation requires the use of truth tables and Karnaugh maps to specify and simplify the cases; see more at Propositional formula. The authors point out the power of "definition by cases":

"...in more complicated examples, definition by cases makes it far easier to establish the (primitive) recursiveness of important functions. This is mainly because there are a variety of processes for defining new relations from old that can be shown to produce new (primitive) recursive relations when applied to (primitive) recursive relations." (Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey 2002:74)

They prove, in particular, that the processes of substitution, graph relation (similar to the identity relation that plucks out (the value of) a particular variable from a list of variables), negation (logical NOT), conjunction (logical AND), disjunction (logical OR), bounded universal quantification, or bounded existential quantification can be used together with definition by cases to create new primitive recursive functions (cf Boolos-Burgess-Jeffrey 2002:74-77).

Notes

  1. ^ The 1963 reference has not been located.
  2. ^ Minsky (1967) does not include the identity operator in his description of primitive recursive functions. Why this is the case is not known.
  3. ^ Various authors use various names for this operation. Kleene calls it: "the schema of definition by substitution. The expression for the ambiguous value of φ is obtained by substitution of expressions for the ambigous values of χ1, . . ., χm for the variables of ψ . . .. the function φ defined by an application of this schema we sometimes write ast Smn(ψ, 1, . . ., χm." (Kleene 1952:220). Knuth names it the "all-important replacement operaton (sometimes called assignment or substitution)", and he symbolizes it with the " ← " arrow, e.g. "m ← n" means the value of variable m is to be replaced by the current value of variable n" (cf Knuth 1973:3).
  4. ^ Kleene's 5 primitive recursion "schema" include the following:
    • (I) zero constant: 0 or may be 0()
    • (II) successor: S(0) = "1", S(1) = "2", etc.
    • (III) projection: Uin ( x1 , ..., xn ) = xi, the xi's are "parameters" fixed throughout the calculation, and Uin project one of them out, the notation \pi_i^n (x_1,\ldots,x_n) = x_i is also used.
    • (IV) substitution φ( x1 , ..., xn ) = ψ ( χ1( x1 , ..., xn ), ..., χm( x1 , ..., xn ))
    • (V) primitive recursion; cf Kleene 1952:219.

References

  • George S. Boolos, John P. Burgess, and Richard C. Jeffrey, 2002, Computability and Logic: Fourth Edition, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK, ISBN 0521 00758 5 paperback.
  • John McCarthy (1960), Recursive Functions of Symbolic Expressions and Their Computation by Machine, Part I, Communications of the ACM, 3, 184-195 (April 1960).
  • Marvin Minsky (1967), Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines, Prentice-Hall Inc, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем сделать НИР

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Counter machine reference model — The Counter machine s reference model is a set of choices and conventions to be used with the Counter machine and other model variants of the Register machine concept. It permits comparisons between models, and serves a didactic function with… …   Wikipedia

  • Register machine — In mathematical logic and theoretical computer science a register machine is a generic class of abstract machines used in a manner similar to a Turing machine. All the models are Turing equivalent. Contents 1 Overview 2 Formal definition 3 …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (M) — NOTOC M M estimator M group M matrix M separation M set M. C. Escher s legacy M. Riesz extension theorem M/M/1 model Maass wave form Mac Lane s planarity criterion Macaulay brackets Macbeath surface MacCormack method Macdonald polynomial Machin… …   Wikipedia

  • Conditional (programming) — Conditional statement redirects here. For the general concept in logic, see Material conditional. In computer science, conditional statements, conditional expressions and conditional constructs are features of a programming language which perform …   Wikipedia

  • Planner (programming language) — Planner (often seen in publications as PLANNER although it is not an acronym) is a programming language designed by Carl Hewitt at MIT, and first published in 1969. First, subsets such as Micro Planner and Pico Planner were implemented, and then… …   Wikipedia

  • Neats vs. scruffies — Artificial intelligence portal Neat and scruffy are labels for two different types of artificial intelligence research. Neats consider that solutions should be elegant, clear and provably correct. Scruffies believe that intelligence is too… …   Wikipedia

  • List of important publications in computer science — This is a list of important publications in computer science, organized by field. Some reasons why a particular publication might be regarded as important: Topic creator – A publication that created a new topic Breakthrough – A publication that… …   Wikipedia

  • Circumscription (logic) — Not to be confused with circumscribe. Circumscription is a non monotonic logic created by John McCarthy to formalize the common sense assumption that things are as expected unless otherwise specified. Circumscription was later used by McCarthy in …   Wikipedia

  • Situation calculus — The situation calculus is a logic formalism designed for representing and reasoning about dynamical domains. It was first introduced by John McCarthy in 1963. The main version of the situational calculus that is presented in this article is based …   Wikipedia

  • literature — /lit euhr euh cheuhr, choor , li treuh /, n. 1. writings in which expression and form, in connection with ideas of permanent and universal interest, are characteristic or essential features, as poetry, novels, history, biography, and essays. 2.… …   Universalium

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”