Category (Kant)

Category (Kant)

In Kant's philosophy, a category is a pure concept of the understanding. A Kantian category is a characteristic of the appearance of any object in general, before it has been experienced. Kant wrote that he wanted to provide "…a word of explanation in regard to the categories. They are concepts of an object in general…." [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", B129, ("Sie sind Begriffe von einem Gegenstande überhaupt")] Kant also wrote that "…pure concepts [Categories] of the understanding…apply to objects of intuition in general…." [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", § 79 ("reine Verstandesbegriffe, welche a priori auf Gegenstände der Anschauung überhaupt gehen")] Such a category is not a classificatory division, as the word is commonly used. It is, instead, the condition of the possibility of objects in general, [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", A 139] that is, objects as such, any and all objects, not specific objects in particular.

Meaning of "Category"

The word comes from the Greek κατηγορία, "katēgoria", meaning "that which can be predicated, or publicly declared and asserted, about something." A category is an attribute, property, quality, or characteristic that can be predicated of a thing. "…I remark concerning the categories…that their logical employment consists in their use as predicates of objects." [Letter from Beck to Kant, June 20, 1797] Kant called them "ontological predicates." [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Judgement", Introduction, V]

Aristotle had claimed that the following ten predicates or categories could be asserted of anything in general: substance, quantity, quality, relation, action, affection (passivity), place, time (date), position, and state.

These are supposed to be the qualities or attributes that can be affirmed of each and every thing in experience. Any particular object that exists in thought must have been able to have the Categories attributed to it as possible predicates because the Categories are the properties, qualities, or characteristics of any possible object in general. The Categories of Aristotle and Kant are the general properties that belong to all things without expressing the peculiar nature of any particular thing. Kant appreciated Aristotle's effort, but said that his table was imperfect because " … as he had no guiding principle, he merely picked them up as they occurred to him..." [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", A 81]

The Categories do not provide knowledge of individual, particular objects. Any object, however, must have Categories as its characteristics if it is to be an object of experience. It is presupposed or assumed that anything that is a specific object must possess Categories as its properties because Categories are predicates of an object in general. An object in general does not have all of the Categories as predicates at one time. For example, a general object cannot have the qualitative Categories of reality and negation at the same time. Similarly, an object in general cannot have both unity and plurality as quantitative predicates at once. The Categories of Modality exclude each other. Therefore, a general object cannot simultaneously have the Categories of possibility/impossibility and existence/non–existence as qualities.

Since the Categories are a list of that which can be said of every object, they are related only to human language. In making a verbal statement about an object, a speaker makes a judgment. A general object, that is, every object, has attributes that are contained in Kant's list of Categories. In a judgment, or verbal statement, the Categories are the predicates that can be asserted of every object and all objects.

The table of judgments

Kant believed that the ability of the human understanding to think about and know an object is the same as the making of a spoken or written judgment about an object. According to him, "Our ability to judge is equivalent to our ability to think." [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", A 80] A judgment is the thought that a thing is known to have a certain quality or attribute. For example, the sentence "The rose is red" is a judgment. Kant created a table of the forms of such judgments as they relate to all objects in general. [Kant, Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", A 71]

*Quantity
**Universal
**Particular
**Singular
*Quality
**Affirmative
**Negative
**Infinite
*Relation
**Categorical
**Hypothetical
**Disjunctive
*Modality
**Problematical
**Assertoric
**Apodictic

This table of judgments was used by Kant as a model for the table of categories.

The table of categories

*Quantity
**Unity
**Plurality
**Totality
*Quality
**Reality
**Negation
**Limitation
*Relation
**Inherence and Subsistence (substance and accident)
**Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)
**Community (reciprocity)
*Modality
**Possibility
**Existence
**Necessity

chemata

Categories are entirely different from the appearances of objects. According to Kant, in order to relate to specific phenomena, categories must be "applied" through time. The way that this is done is called a Schema.

Criticism

Schopenhauer, in his criticism of the Kantian philosophy, found many errors in Kant's use of the Categories of Quality, Quantity, Relation, and Modality. Schopenhauer also noted that in accordance with Kant's claim, non-human animals would not be able to know objects. Animals would only know impressions on their sense organs, which Kant mistakenly calls perception.

Common misunderstanding

Kant's Categories are commonly misunderstood as being forms that exist in the mind from birth. They are seen as being latent mental possibilities that become active during sense experience. However, Kant's Categories are really only the qualities or characteristics that are shared by all objects in general. The most general, non–specific properties of objects are the Kantian Categories. They are linguistic because they are the attributes that can be verbally predicated or said of all objects in general, not of specific objects.Fact|date=July 2008 ["Thus there arise precisely as many pure concepts of understanding applying to "a priori" objects of intuition in general [überhaupt] , as in the preceding table there were logical functions involved in all possible [allen möglichen] judgments." "Critique of Pure Reason", A 80. Our contemporary definition of "category" is "a division into groups." For Kant and Aristotle, though, the meaning of the word was in accordance with its original definition: "that which can be said about objects in general, or all possible objects."]

Notes

Bibliography

*Kant,Immanuel, "Critique of Pure Reason", Hackett, 1996, ISBN 0-87220-257-7
*Mill, John Stuart, "A System of Logic", University Press of the Pacific, 2002, ISBN 1-4102-0252-6
*Zweig, Arnulf, edited by, "Kant: Philosophical Correspondence 1759–99", University of Chicago Press, 1967

ee also

* Categories (Aristotle)
* Category of being
* Schema (Kant)
* Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata
* Critique of Pure Reason

Notes


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Поможем написать курсовую

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Category — may refer to: *Category (philosophy) *taxonomic category Taxonomic rank *Category (grammar) *Category (mathematics) * Categories (Aristotle) *Category (Kant) *Categories (Stoic) *Categories (game), a game involving naming categories of things… …   Wikipedia

  • Category of being — In metaphysics (in particular, ontology), the different kinds or ways of being are called categories of being or simply categories. To investigate the categories of being is to determine the most fundamental and the broadest classes of entities.… …   Wikipedia

  • Kant: Critique of Judgement — Patrick Gardiner Kant’s third Critique, the Critique of Judgement, was published in 1790 and was intended as he himself put it to bring his “entire critical undertaking to a close.” So conceived, it was certainly in part designed to build upon… …   History of philosophy

  • Category — • The term was transferred by Aristotle from its forensic meaning (procedure in legal accusation) to its logical use as attribution of a subject Catholic Encyclopedia. Kevin Knight. 2006. Category     Category …   Catholic encyclopedia

  • Immanuel Kant — Kant redirects here. For other uses, see Kant (disambiguation). See also: Kant (surname) Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant Full name Immanuel Kant Born 22 April 1724 …   Wikipedia

  • category — /kat i gawr ee, gohr ee/, n., pl. categories. 1. any general or comprehensive division; a class. 2. a classificatory division in any field of knowledge, as a phylum or any of its subdivisions in biology. 3. Metaphys. a. (in Aristotelian… …   Universalium

  • Kant, Immanuel — born April 22, 1724, Königsberg, Prussia died Feb. 12, 1804, Königsberg German philosopher, one of the foremost thinkers of the Enlightenment. The son of a saddler, he studied at the university in Königsberg and taught there as privatdocent… …   Universalium

  • Schema (Kant) — In Kantian philosophy, a schema (plural: schemata ) is the procedural rule by which a category or pure, non empirical concept is associated with a mental image of an object. It is supposedly produced by the imagination through the pure form of… …   Wikipedia

  • Schopenhauer's criticism of Kant's schemata — is part of Schopenhauer s criticism of the Kantian philosophy which was published in 1819. In the appendix to the first volume of his main work, Arthur Schopenhauer attempted to assign the psychological cause of Kant s doctrines of the categories …   Wikipedia

  • Immanuel Kant — Nacimiento …   Wikipedia Español

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”