Ellsberg paradox

Ellsberg paradox

The Ellsberg paradox is a paradox in decision theory and experimental economics in which people's choices violate the expected utility hypothesis.Citation |last=Ellsberg|first=Daniel|authorlink=Daniel Ellsberg|journal=Quarterly Journal of Economics|volume=75|number=4|title=Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms|year=1961|pages=643–669] It is generally taken to be evidence for ambiguity aversion. The paradox was popularized by Daniel Ellsberg, although a version of it was noted considerably earlier by John Maynard Keynes (Keynes 1921, pp.75–76, p.315, ft.2).

The paradox

Suppose you have an urn containing 30 red balls and 60 other balls that are either black or yellow. You don't know how many black or yellow balls there are, but that the total number of black balls plus the total number of yellow balls equals 60. The balls are well mixed so that each individual ball is as likely to be drawn as any other. You are now given a choice between two gambles:

Also you are given the choice between these two gambles (about a different draw from the same urn):

Since the prizes are exactly the same, it follows that you will "prefer" Gamble A to Gamble B "if, and only if", you believe that drawing a red ball is more likely than drawing a black ball (according to expected utility theory). Also, there would be no clear preference between the choices if you thought that a red ball was as likely as a black ball. Similarly it follows that you will "prefer" Gamble C to Gamble D "if, and only if", you believe that drawing a red or yellow ball is more likely than drawing a black or yellow ball. If drawing a red ball is more likely than drawing a black ball, then drawing a red or yellow ball is also more likely than drawing a black or yellow ball. So, supposing you "prefer" Gamble A to Gamble B, it follows that you will also "prefer" Gamble C to Gamble D. And, supposing instead that you "prefer" Gamble D to Gamble C, it follows that you will also "prefer" Gamble B to Gamble A.

When surveyed, however, most people "strictly prefer" Gamble A to Gamble B and Gamble D to Gamble C. Therefore, some assumptions of the expected utility theory are violated.

Mathematical demonstration

Mathematically, your estimated probabilities of each color ball can be represented as: "R", "Y", and "B". If you "strictly prefer" Gamble A to Gamble B, by utility theory, it is presumed this preference is reflected by the expected utilities of the two gambles: specifically, it must be the case that

: R cdot U($100) + (1-R) cdot U($0) > Bcdot U($100) + (1-B) cdot U($0)

where U(cdot) is your utility function. If U($100) > U($0) (you strictly prefer $100 to nothing), this simplifies to:

: R > B ;

If you also strictly prefer Gamble D to Gamble C, the following inequality is similarly obtained:

: Bcdot U($100) + Ycdot U($100) + R cdot U($0) > R cdot U($100) + Ycdot U($100) + B cdot U($0)

This simplifies to:

: B > R ;

This contradiction indicates that your preferences are inconsistent with expected-utility theory.

Generality of the paradox

Note that the result holds regardless of your utility function. Indeed, the amount of the payoff is likewise irrelevant. Whichever gamble you choose, the prize for winning it is the same, and the cost of losing it is the same (no cost), so ultimately, there are only two outcomes: you receive a specific amount of money, or you receive nothing. Therefore it is sufficient to assume that you prefer receiving some money to receiving nothing (and in fact, this assumption is not necessary &mdash; in the mathematical treatment above, it was assumed "U"($100) > "U"($0), but a contradiction can still be obtained for "U"($100) < "U"($0) and for "U"($100) = "U"($0)).

In addition, the result holds regardless of your risk aversion. All the gambles involve risk. By choosing Gamble D, you have a 1 in 3 chance of receiving nothing, and by choosing Gamble A, you have a 2 in 3 chance of receiving nothing. If Gamble A was less risky than Gamble B, it would follow that Gamble C was less risky than Gamble D (and vice versa), so, risk is not averted in this way.

However, because the exact chances of winning are known for Gambles A and D, and not known for Gambles B and C, this can be taken as evidence for some sort of ambiguity aversion which cannot be accounted for in expected utility theory. It has been demonstrated that this phenomenon occurs only when the choice set permits comparison of the ambiguous proposition with a less vague proposition (but not when ambiguous propositions are evaluated in isolation)Citation | last1=Fox | first1= Craig R. |last2=Tversky |first2=Amos |authorlink1=Craig R. Fox |authorlink2=Amos Tversky|year=1995|title=Ambiguity Aversion and Comparative Ignorance|journal=Quarterly Journal of Economics|volume=110|number=3|pages=585&ndash;603] .

Possible explanations

There have been various attempts to provide decision-theoretic explanations of Ellsberg's observation. Since the probabilistic information available to the decision-maker is incomplete, these attempts sometimes focus on quantifying the non-probabilistic ambiguity which the decision-maker faces. That is, these alternative approaches sometimes suppose that the agent formulates a subjective (though not necessarily Bayesian) probability for possible outcomes.

One such attempt is based on info-gap decision theory. The agent is told precise probabilities of some outcomes, though the practical meaning of the probability numbers is not entirely clear. For instance, in the gambles discussed above, the probability of a red ball is 30/90, which is a precise number. Nonetheless, the agent may not distinguish, intuitively, between this and, say, 30/91. No probability information whatsoever is provided regarding other outcomes, so the agent has very unclear subjective impressions of these probabilities.

In light of the ambiguity in the probabilities of the outcomes, the agent is unable to evaluate a precise expected utility. Consequently, a choice based on "maximizing" the expected utility is also impossible. The info-gap approach supposes that the agent implicitly formulates info-gap models for the subjectively uncertain probabilities. The agent then tries to satisfice the expected utility and to maximize the robustness against uncertainty in the imprecise probabilities. This robust-satisficing approach can be developed explicitly to show that the choices of decision-makers should display precisely the preference reversal which Ellsberg observed.cite book|last=Ben-Haim|first=Yakov|authorlink=Yakov Ben-Haim|year=2006|title=Info-gap Decision Theory: Decisions Under Severe Uncertainty|edition=2nd edition|publisher=Academic Press|page=section 11.1|isbn=0123735521]

An obvious explanation is that people prefer the bet where cheating can be detected.Fact|date=September 2008 If the urn is turned over and the marbles counted, a cheat on the red marbles would be detected, because there must be 30. However, if, for example, no black marbles and 60 yellow ones are found, one cannot find out whether this was an honest coincidence or cheating. Thus bet A requires less trust than bet B and should be preferred.

ee also

*Allais paradox
*Experimental economics
*Utility theory

References

* cite book
last = Anand
first = Paul
authorlink = Paul Anand
title = Foundations of Rational Choice Under Risk
publisher = Oxford University Press, USA
year = 1993
pages =
isbn = 0198233035

* Keynes, John Maynard. (1921). "A Treatise on Probability". Macmillan, London.


Wikimedia Foundation. 2010.

Игры ⚽ Нужен реферат?

Look at other dictionaries:

  • Ellsberg-Paradox — Das Ellsberg Paradoxon ist ein aus der Entscheidungstheorie bekanntes Phänomen der Entscheidung unter Unsicherheit. Wenn Menschen sich zwischen zwei Optionen entscheiden müssen, und nur bei einer Option die Wahrscheinlichkeitsverteilung bekannt… …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Paradox — Ein Paradoxon oder Paradox (altgriechisch παράδοξον, von παρα , para – gegen und δόξα, dóxa – Meinung, Ansicht), auch Paradoxie (παραδοξία) und in der Mehrzahl Paradoxa g …   Deutsch Wikipedia

  • Daniel Ellsberg — in 2006 Born April 7, 1931 (1931 04 07) (age 80) Education …   Wikipedia

  • Allais paradox — The Allais paradox is a choice problem designed by Maurice Allais to show an inconsistency of actual observed choices with the predictions of expected utility theory. Contents 1 Statement of the Problem 2 Mathematical proof of inconsistency 2.1… …   Wikipedia

  • Эффект неоднозначности — Эффект неоднозначности  это когнитивное искажение, в котором принятие решения страдает из за недостатка информации или неоднозначности. Эффект предполагает, что люди стремятся выбрать решение, для которого вероятность благоприятного исхода… …   Википедия

  • List of paradoxes — This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. Note that many of the listed paradoxes have a clear resolution see Quine s Classification of Paradoxes.Logical, non mathematical* Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an… …   Wikipedia

  • Generalized expected utility — The expected utility model developed by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern dominated decision theory from its formulation in 1944 until the late 1970s, not only as a prescriptive, but also as a descriptive model, despite powerful criticism… …   Wikipedia

  • Список парадоксов — …   Википедия

  • List of statistics topics — Please add any Wikipedia articles related to statistics that are not already on this list.The Related changes link in the margin of this page (below search) leads to a list of the most recent changes to the articles listed below. To see the most… …   Wikipedia

  • List of mathematics articles (E) — NOTOC E E₇ E (mathematical constant) E function E₈ lattice E₈ manifold E∞ operad E7½ E8 investigation tool Earley parser Early stopping Earnshaw s theorem Earth mover s distance East Journal on Approximations Eastern Arabic numerals Easton s… …   Wikipedia

Share the article and excerpts

Direct link
Do a right-click on the link above
and select “Copy Link”